Defining a surreal hyperexponential

Vincent Bagayoko

Département de Mathématique

Université de Mons, Le Pentagone

20, Place du Parc

B-7000 Mons, Belgique

CNRS, LIX

Campus de l'École polytechnique

1, rue Honoré d'Estienne d'Orves

Bâtiment Alan Turing, CS35003

91120 Palaiseau, France

Email: vincent.bagayoko@lilo.org

Joris van der Hoeven

CNRS, Department of Mathematics

Simon Fraser University

8888 University Drive

Burnaby, British Columbia

V5A 1S6, Canada

CNRS, LIX

Campus de l'École polytechnique

1, rue Honoré d'Estienne d'Orves

Bâtiment Alan Turing, CS35003

91120 Palaiseau, France

Email: vdhoeven@lix.polytechnique.fr

Vincenzo Mantova

School of Mathematics,

University of Leeds, Leeds

LS2 9JT, United Kingdom

Email: V.L.Mantova@leeds.ac.uk

Conway's class of surreal numbers admits a rich structure: it forms a totally ordered real closed field with an exponential functions and a derivation. The aim of this note is to construct a surreal solution to the functional equation with good properties.

1.Introduction

Let be Conway's class of surreal numbers. It is well known that admits a rich structure: Conway showed that forms a real closed field and Gonshor also defined an exponential function on that satisfies the same first order theory as the usual exponential function on the reals. Following Conway's tradition, all numbers will understood to be surreal in what follows.

The aim of this note is to define a bijective function on the class of positive infinitely large numbers, which is strictly increasing and satisfies the functional equation

(1)

for all . Since this equation admits many solutions, the main difficulty is to single out a particular solution that will be most “natural” in a way that needs to be made precise.

The function is said hyperexponential and it is the first non-trivial hyperexponential in the transfinite sequence of iterated exponentials

The corresponding reciprocals are called hyperlogarithms:

It is natural to require such more general hyperexponentials to satisfy for all ordinals and . Similarly, .

There are known real analytic solutions of (1) with good properties [12, 6], even though there does not seem to exist any meaningful “most natural” solution. It is also well known that fractional iterates of and can be defined in terms of and : given , we take and .

From a formal perspective, hyperexponentials and hyperseries were studied in detail by Schmeling and van der Hoeven [14]: they generalized transseries to include formal counterparts , of , for [14]. This yields in particular a natural hyperexponential on the set of positive infinitely large transseries. More recently, van den Dries, van der Hoeven and Kaplan [7] constructed the field of logarithmic hyperseries with for all , with corresponding natural hyperlogarithms . The ultimate goal [11, 2] is to produce a field of hyperseries with all hyperexponentials and to construct an isomorphism . This work can be considered as another step in this direction, by constructing a natural .

Surreal numbers and transseries
It is well known that surreal numbers can be written as infinite series

where denotes the class of surreal monomials and the coefficients are real. In particular, is isomorphic to the Hahn field of formal power series. Together with the exponential function, even admits the structure of a field of transseries in the sense of [14]; see [4].

We will freely use notations from [1, 11] when dealing with such transseries. In particular, the support of is defined as and its infinite part as . Here we used Hardy's notation for . Similarly, we set . We also define , , and . Finally, we write if , in which case we say that is a truncation of .

Defining exponentials
Consider a number and decompose it as with , , and . Then the functional equation of yields

(2)

where is the usual exponential in and . In order to define on , this relation shows that it would have sufficed to define it on . In addition, it can be shown that bijectively maps the class to the class . Our process to define is similar, with different subclasses and in the roles of and . The class is defined below and is the class of log-atomic numbers, i.e. numbers such that for all .

Surreal substructures
It turns out that each of the classes , , , and are examples of so-called surreal substructures, which were extensively studied in [3]. Let us quickly recall a few basic facts; see also section 2.

Besides the usual ordering, the class of surreal numbers admits a well-founded partial order called the simplicity relation. A surreal substructure is a subclass of that is isomorphic to for the induced relations by and on . Equivalently, this means that for any subsets of with , the cut

in admits a -minimum which is then denoted . We call a cut representation in . We extend this notation to the case when are classes, provided indeed exists. If , then we let

Then . Moreover, for any cut in containing (such as ), the set (resp. ) is cofinal (resp. coinitial) with respect to (resp. ).

Important examples of surreal substructures include , the class of strictly positive numbers, the class of positive infinitely large numbers, the classes and of monomials and infinite monomials, the class of purely infinite numbers, and the class of infinitesimal numbers.

Truncated numbers
Assume that has been defined for some positive purely infinite number . For sufficiently small , we wish to define using Taylor series expansion:

(3)

The successive derivatives can be defined in as ordinary (and so-called logarithmic) transseries applied to :

It can be shown that (3) converges formally, provided that . More generally, consider with for a certain . Assuming (1), this means that , which allows us to define

(4)

and set

(5)

It follows that it is sufficient to define at numbers with

where . Those numbers are said to be truncated and we will write for the class of all truncated numbers. It turns out that is a surreal substructure.

Defining hyperexponentials
Our definition of proceeds in three stages:

  1. We first define on . For any two positive purely infinite numbers with , we have . By the functional equation, we should have . We deduce that for , the number should lie in the cut in where

    The simplest way to ensure this is to define

    for all .

  2. We next extend to . Similar arguments and the simplicity heuristic impose

    where is a function group to be defined in Section 2. Here , , and (3) play a similar role as , , and (2) when extending the definition of .

  3. We finally extend the definition of to by relying on (4) and (5).

2.Equations and convex partitions

Before we define , let us briefly recall a general method to define surreal substructures using convex partitions. For more details, see [3, Section 6].

Uniform equations
Let be a surreal substructure and be a function. Let be functions defined for cut representations in and such that is a cut representation in whenever is a cut representation in . We say that is an equation of if, for all , we have

We say that the equation is uniform if we have whenever is a cut representation in . For instance, by [9, Theorem 3.2], for , the following equation for the translation by is uniform:

(6)

Remark 1. Assume that has an equation with

This is in particular the case if and for all . Then we claim that is strictly increasing. To see this, consider with . By [3, Proposition 4.6], there is a -maximal element of with , and we have or . We treat the first case, the other one being symmetric. Since and , we have so there is with . We have . A similar argument yields , so .

Convex partitions
Let be a surreal substructure and let be a partition of into convex subclasses, each of which admits a cofinal and coinitial subset. We refer to as a thin convex partition of . For , we let denote the unique member of containing . We also write for any subclass of . We say that an element is -simple if it is the -minimum of its class . This is equivalent to the existence of a cut in with and .

Then the class of -simple elements forms a surreal substructure which is contained in . For , we have .

Function groups
A function group on a surreal substructure is a group of strictly increasing bijections under functional composition. We regard elements of as actions on and sometimes write and for rather than and . For such a function group , the collection of classes

is a thin convex partition of and we define .

For , the relation is a partial order on . We will frequently rely on the elementary fact that is partially bi-ordered, i.e. that we have

Common function groups
As an example, we can obtain the previous structures as the classes for actions of the following function groups acting on , or . For and , we define

acting on or
acting on or
acting on or

We define

We then have the following list of identities [3, Section 7.1]:

For , we will denote the unique log-atomic element of and we will denote the unique element of lying in . We have .

3.Logarithmic transseries and hyperseries

Let denote the field of logarithmic hyperseries from [7]. For each , we define . Recall that stands for the set of series with Noetherian support in the partially ordered set . We may consider elements of as bivariate series that are logarithmic transseries with respect to and ordinary series with respect to .

Lemma 2. Consider a series such that the substitution of by in vanishes for all in . Then .

Proof. Assume for contradiction that . Write and let be minimal with . Since is Noetherian as a series in , the set is well based and admits a largest element . Taking sufficiently small such that , it follows that , whence .

Lemma 3. Given integers and , we have

(7)

as an identity in .

Proof. The left and right hand sides of (7) are clearly Noetherian series in . For any in , the following Taylor series expansions hold in :

Subtracting both expansions, the identity (7) holds for substituted by in . We conclude by Lemma 2.

In [7], we defined the field , as well as a hyperlogarithmic function on for which with . Let . Then logarithmic transseries in can be considered as elements in and the successive derivatives of with respect to are given by

For any , we have

whence

For in , this allows us to define using the Taylor series expansion

(8)

Lemma 4. The following identity holds in :

(9)

Proof. The left hand side is well defined by (8) for in . The fact that (9) holds for substituted by in follows from the usual rules of iterated derivatives of inverse functions. For a detailed proof, we refer to [14, section 6.4]. We conclude by Lemma 2.

4.Hyperexponentials of truncated numbers

We recursively define for positive purely infinite numbers by

(10)

Proposition 5. The function defines a strictly increasing bijection . Moreover, the previous equation is uniform.

Proof. The function is well-defined and strictly increasing by Remark 1. The uniformity of the equation follows immediately.

Let denote the partial inverse function of and prove that is defined on by induction on . Let such that is contained . Since is injective, its inverse is defined on . Let

This number is well defined since is strictly increasing and for , we have . By uniformity, we have where . In order to conclude that , it therefore suffices to show that lies in the cut . We have by (10) and by definition of , whence since . We conclude by induction that is surjective.

We next identify the class of truncated numbers. For , we consider the following convex class

Proposition 6. The classes for form a thin convex partition of .

Proof. Given , it is clear that the class is convex and that it contains . Note that for , we have . Let with . We claim that . If , then we have , which yields the result. Assume that . Assume for contradiction that there are and with and . Given , there is a number with . Therefore are dominated by , whence . This proves that and symmetric arguments yield : a contradiction. This proves our claim. It only remains to see that the class admits a cofinal and coinitial subset for any . Indeed, we can take as examples of such sets.

Corollary 7. The class is a surreal substructure.

Let and let denote the -supremum of truncations of (i.e. series with ) with . In particular, we have since . We see that satisfies and . Write and . By -maximality of , we have so , or equivalently . We deduce that is the -minimum, hence -minimum of , so . We also see that for and , we have . Since is a surreal substructure, we may use recursion on to define

(11)

Proposition 8. The equation (11) is uniform and is a strictly increasing function .

Proof. Since is a surreal substructure, the definition, strict monotonicity and uniformity follow by Remark 1. For , we have since on . We deduce that is -simple, hence log-atomic.

By [4, Lemma 2.4], for every infinite monomial , we have

(12)

Proposition 9. We have .

Proof. We prove this by induction on . Let such that this holds on . Note that for all and . We have , so

We deduce that

Since , we may apply (12). We also note that and are mutually cofinal and coinitial for all to obtain

We have , so and . We clearly have . We deduce that . By induction, the relation is valid on .

Proposition 10. For , we have .

Proof. We prove this by induction on . Let be such that this holds on . For , we have , and there is with . We deduce that . In particular, we have so . This proves that is cofinal with respect to . For and , we have where , so is cofinal with respect to . Symmetric arguments yield that and are mutually coinitial. We conclude that .

Proposition 11. The function is bijective. Its reciprocal admits the following uniform equation on :

Proof. Noticing that for all , this follows from the same arguments as in Proposition 5.

5.Hyperexponentials of arbitrary numbers

The field of logarithmic hyperseries of [7] is a subfield of the class of all well-based transseries in an infinitely large variable . Both and the class of all transseries are closed under derivation and under composition [8, 10, 14]. For every positive infinite number , there also exists an evaluation embedding such that for all : see [5].

Given , let be the unique truncated series with . If , then there is a smallest number with

Write . With as in section 3, we define for every :

Substitution of for in (8) allows us to extend the definition of by

and

Proposition 12. For all , we have

Proof. If , then this is Proposition 9. Otherwise, we have and , whence and

Inversely, consider an arbitrary positive infinite number . Then there exists a such that for some log-atomic and . We extend the definition of to any such number by

In view of Lemma 3, the value of does not depend on the choice of . Note also that this definition indeed extends our previous definition of on .

Proposition 13. For all , we have

Proof. With as above (while taking ), we have

where because of Proposition 9.

Proposition 14. For any , we have .

Proof. Let be such that , where and . Let us first consider the special case when . Since is log-atomic, we have . From Lemma 4, it therefore follows that inside . The result follows by specializing this relation at . If , then by Proposition 13. Applying the result for the special case when , we have . We conclude by Proposition 12.

In particular, the function is surjective. We next prove that it is strictly increasing, concluding our proof that is a strictly increasing bijection with reciprocal .

Lemma 15. For with , we have .

Proof. Note that , so it is enough to prove that for all . For such , there is with , and

where is infinitesimal. So , whence .

Lemma 16. For and with , there is with

Proof. Write and where and let with . Writing for , we have . We deduce that

Proposition 17. The function is strictly increasing on .

Proof. Let with . If , then we get by Lemma 15. Otherwise, we have so by Lemma 16, there are and with

Since , we conclude that , whence .

Corollary 18. The function is bijective, with reciprocal .

Bibliography

[1]

M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. Asymptotic Differential Algebra and Model Theory of Transseries. Number 195 in Annals of Mathematics studies. Princeton University Press, 2017.

[2]
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. On numbers, germs, and transseries. In Proc. Int. Cong. of Math. 2018 , volume 1, pages 1–24. Rio de Janeiro, 2018.

[3]
V. Bagayoko and J. van der Hoeven. Surreal substructures. Technical Report, HAL, 2019. http://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02151377 .

[4]

A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Surreal numbers, derivations and transseries. JEMS, 20(2):339–390, 2018.

[5]

A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Transseries as germs of surreal functions. Trans. of the AMS, 371:3549–3592, 2019.

[6]

M. Boshernitzan. Hardy fields, existence of transexponential functions. Æquationes Math., 30:258–280, 1986.

[7]

L. van den Dries, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Logarithmic hyperseries. Trans. of the AMS, 372(7):5199–5241, 2019.

[8]

J. Écalle. Introduction aux fonctions analysables et preuve constructive de la conjecture de Dulac. Hermann, collection: Actualités mathématiques, 1992.

[9]

H. Gonshor. An Introduction to the Theory of Surreal Numbers. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1986.

[10]

J. van der Hoeven. Automatic asymptotics. PhD thesis, École polytechnique, Palaiseau, France, 1997.

[11]

J. van der Hoeven. Transseries and real differential algebra, volume 1888 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, 2006.

[12]

H. Kneser. Reelle analytische Lösungen der Gleichung und verwandter Funktionalgleichungen. Jour. f. d. reine und angewandte Math., 187(1/2):56–67, 1950.

[13]

S. Kuhlmann and M. Matusinski. The exponential-logarithmic equivalence classes of surreal numbers. Order 32, pages 53–68, 2015.

[14]

M. C. Schmeling. Corps de transséries. PhD thesis, Université Paris-VII, 2001.