|
A. vincent.bagayoko@umons.ac.be
B. vdhoeven@lix.polytechnique.fr
. This article has
been written using GNU TeXmacs [27].
For any ordinal ,
we show how to define a hyperexponential
and a
hyperlogarithm
on the class
of positive infinitely large surreal numbers. Such functions are
archetypes of extremely fast and slowly growing functions at infinity.
We also show that the surreal numbers form a so-called hyperserial field
for our definition.
The ordered field of surreal numbers was
introduced by Conway in [11]. Conway originally used
transfinite recursion to define both the surreal numbers (henceforth
called numbers), the ordering on No, and the
ring operations. For any two sets
and
of numbers with
(i.e.
for all
and
), there exists a number
with
and all numbers can be obtained in this way. Given
and
, we have
and similar recursive formulas exist for ,
and for deciding whether
,
, and
. It is truly remarkable that
turns out to be a totally ordered real-closed
field for such “simple” definitions [11]. The
bracket
is called the Conway bracket.
Using this bracket, we obtain a surreal number in any traditional
Dedekind cut, which allows us to embed
into
. In addition,
contains all ordinal numbers
so is actually a proper class.
An interesting question is which other operations from calculus can be
extended to the surreal numbers. Gonshor has shown how to extend the
real exponential function to the surreal numbers [19] and
the resulting exponential field turns out to be
elementarily equivalent to
[13].
Berarducci and Mantova recently defined a derivation with respect to
on the surreals [9], again with
good model-theoretic properties [2]. In collaboration with
Mantova, the authors constructed a surreal solution to the functional
equation
which is a bijection of onto itself [6].
We call
a hyperexponential and its
functional inverse
a hyperlogarithm.
The first goal of this paper is to extend the results from [6]
to the construction of hyperexponentials of any
ordinal force
,
together with their functional inverses
.
If
is a successor ordinal, then
satisfies the functional equation
Our second goal is to show that these hyperexponentials are
“well-behaved” in the sense that they endow
with the structure of a hyperserial field in the sense of [5].
Whereas it is natural to study surreal exponentiation and differentiation, it may seem more exotic to define and investigate the properties of surreal hyperexponentials and hyperlogarithms. In fact, the main motivation behind our work is a conjecture by the second author [26, p. 16] and a research program that was laid out in [1] for proving this conjecture. The ultimate goal is to expose the deep connections between two types of mathematical infinities: numerical infinities and growth rates at infinity. Let us briefly recall the rationale behind this connection.
Cantor's ordinal numbers provide us with a way to count beyond all natural numbers and to keep counting beyond the size of any set. However, ordinal arithmetic is rather poor in the sense that we have no subtraction or division and that addition and multiplication do not satisfy the usual laws of arithmetic, such as commutativity. We may regard Conway's surreal numbers as providing a calculus with Cantor's ordinal numbers which does extend the usual calculus with real numbers. In this sense, Conway managed to construct the ultimate framework for computations with numerical infinities.
Another source for computations with infinitely large quantities stems
from the study of growth rates of real functions at infinity. The first
major results towards a systematic asymptotic calculus of this kind are
due to Hardy in [21, 22], based on earlier
ideas by du Bois-Reymond [15, 16, 17].
Hardy defined an -function
to be a function constructed from
and the real
numbers
using the field operations,
exponentiation, and logarithms. He proved that the germs of
-functions at infinity form a totally ordered
field. The framework of
-functions
is suitable for asymptotic analysis since we have an ordering for
comparing the growth at infinity of any two such functions. This is
often rephrased by saying that
-functions
have a regular growth at infinity.
Hardy also observed [21, p. 22] that “The only scales
of infinity that are of any practical importance in analysis are those
which may be constructed by means of the logarithmic and exponential
functions.” In other words, Hardy suggested that the framework of
-functions not only allows
for the development of a systematic asymptotic calculus, but that this
framework is also sufficient for all “practical” purposes.
Alas, there are several “holes”. First of all, the framework
is not closed under various useful operations such as functional
inversion and integration. Secondly, the framework does not contain any
functions of extremely fast or slow growth at infinity, like
and
, although
such functions naturally appear in the analysis of certain algorithms.
For instance, the best known algorithm for multiplying two polynomials
of degree
in
runs in
time
; see [23].
This raises the question how to construct a truly universal framework
for computations with regular functions at infinity. Our next candidate
is the class of transseries. A transseries is a formal object
that is constructed from (with
) and the real numbers, using exponentiation,
logarithms, and infinite sums. One example of a transseries is
Depending on conditions satisfied by their supports, there are different
types of transseries. The first constructions of fields of transseries
are due to Dahn and Göring [12] and Écalle [18]. More general constructions were proposed subsequently by
the second author and his former student Schmeling [24, 25, 29]. Clearly, any -function is a transseries, but the class of
transseries is also closed under integration and functional inversion,
contrary to the class of
-functions.
However, the class of transseries still does not contain any
hyperexponential or hyperlogarithmic elements like
or
. In our quest for a truly
universal framework for asymptotic analysis, we are thus lead to look
beyond: a hyperseries is a formal object that is constructed
from
and the real numbers using exponentiation,
logarithms, infinite sums, as well as hyperexponentials
and hyperlogarithms
of any force
. The hyperexponentials
and the hyperlogarithms
are required to satisfy
functional equations
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
where . For
in Cantor normal form with
,
we also define
and we require that
![]() |
It is non-trivial to construct fields of hyperseries in which these and
several other technical properties (see section 4 below)
are satisfied. This was first accomplished by Schmeling for
hyperexponentials and hyperlogarithms
of finite force
.
The general case was tackled in [14, 5].
The construction of general hyperseries relies on the definition of an
abstract notion of hyperserial fields. Whereas the hyperseries
that we are really after should actually be hyperseries in an
infinitely large variable ,
abstract hyperserial fields potentially contain hyperseries that can not
be written as infinite expressions in
.
In the present paper, we define hyperexponentials
and hyperlogarithms
on
for all ordinals
and show that this provides
with the structure of an abstract hyperserial
field. Moreover, any hyperseries
in
can naturally be evaluated at
to
produce a surreal number
.
The conjecture from [26, p. 16] states that,
for a sufficiently general notion of “hyperseries in
”, all surreal numbers can
actually be obtained in this way. We plan to prove this and the
conjecture in a follow-up paper.
Our main goal is to define hyperexponentials for
any ordinal
and to show that
is a hyperserial field for these hyperexponentials. Since our
construction builds on quite some previous work, the paper starts with
three sections of reminders.
In section 2, we recall basic facts about well-based series
and surreal numbers. In particular, we recall that any surreal number
can be regarded as a well-based series
with real coefficients . The
corresponding group of monomials
consists of
those positive numbers
that are of the form
for certain subsets
and
of
with
.
Section 3 is devoted to the theory of surreal substructures
from [4]. One distinctive feature of the class of surreal
numbers is that it comes with a partial, well-founded order , which is called the simplicity
relation. The Conway bracket can then be characterized by the fact that,
for any sets
and
of surreal numbers with
,
there exists a unique
-minimal
number
with
. For many interesting subclasses
of
, it turns out that the
restrictions of
and
to
give rise to a structure
that is isomorphic to
. Such
classes
are called surreal
substructures of
and they come with their
own Conway bracket
.
In section 4, we recall the definition of hyperserial
fields from [5] and the main results on how to construct
such fields. One major fact from [5] on which we heavily
rely is that the construction of hyperserial fields can be reduced to
the construction of hyperserial skeletons. In the context of
the present paper, this means that it suffices to define the
hyperlogarithms only for very special, so called
-atomic elements.
In the case when , the
-atomic elements are simply the
monomials in
and the definition of the general
logarithm on
indeed reduces to the definition of
the logarithm on
: given
, we write
, where
,
and
is infinitesimal,
and we take
. This very
special case will be considered in more detail in section 5.
In the case when , the
-atomic elements of
are those elements
such that
is a monomial for every
.
The construction of
on
then reduces to the construction of
on the class
of
-atomic
numbers. This particular case was first dealt with in [6]
and this paper can be used as an introduction to the more general
results in the present paper.
For general ordinals , we say
that
is
-atomic
if
is a monomial for every
. The advantage of restricting ourselves to
such numbers
when defining hyperlogarithms is
that
only needs to verify few requirements with
respect to the ordering. This makes it possible to define
using the fairly simple recursive formula
where range over
-atomic
numbers with
and
;
see also (7.1).
In section 6, we prove that this definition is warranted
and that the resulting functions satisfy the
axioms of hyperserial skeletons from [5, Section 3]. Our
proof proceeds by induction on
and also relies
on the fact that the class
of
-atomic numbers actually forms a surreal
substructure of
. Our main
result is the following theorem:
the structure of a confluent hyperserial skeleton in the
sense of [5]. Consequently, we may uniquely extend
to
in a way that gives
the structure of a confluent hyperserial field.
Moreover, for each ordinal
,
the extended function
is bijective.
Our final section 7 is devoted to further identities that
illustrate the interplay between the hyperexponential and
hyperlogarithmic functions and the simplicity relation
on
. We also prove the
following more symmetric variant of (1.5):
where again range over the
-atomic numbers with
and
. An interesting open
question is whether there exists an easy argument that would allow us to
use (1.6) instead of (1.5) as a definition of
.
Let be a (possibly class-sized) linearly ordered
abelian group. We write
for the class
of functions
whose support
is a well-based set, i.e. a set which is well-ordered with
respect to the reverse order .
We see elements of
as
formal well-based series
,
where
denotes the coefficient
of
in
,
for each
. If
, then we define
to be the dominant monomial of
. For
,
we let
and we write
. We say that a series
is a
truncation of
and we write
if
.
The relation
is a well-founded partial order on
with minimum
.
By [20], the class is an ordered
field under the pointwise sum
the Cauchy product
(where each sum has finite support), and where
the positive cone
is given by
The identification of with the formal series
induces an ordered group embedding
.
We next define the following asymptotic relations on :
The relation extends the ordering on
. For non-zero
we actually have
(resp.
, resp.
) if and only if
(resp.
,
resp.
). We
finally define
Series in ,
and
are respectively called purely
large, infinitesimal, and positive infinite.
Let be a family in
,
We say that
is well-based if
is well-based, and
is finite for all
.
In that case, we may define the sum of
by
If is another field of well-based series and
is
-linear,
then we say that
is strongly linear if
for every well-based family
in
, the family
is
well-based, with
We denote by the class of ordinal numbers.
Following [19], we define
to be the
class of sign sequences
of ordinal length .
The terms
are called the signs of
and we write
for the length
of
. Given two numbers
, we define
We call the simplicity relation on
and note that
is
well-founded. See [4, Section 2] for more details about the
interaction between
and the ordered field
structure of
.
Recall that the Conway bracket is characterized by the fact that, for
any sets and
of
surreal numbers with
, there
exists a unique
-minimal
number
with
.
Conversely, given a number
,
we define
Then can canonically be written as
The structure contains an isomorphic copy of
by identifying each ordinal
with the constant sequence
of length
. We will write
to state that
is either an ordinal or the class
of ordinals.
For , we write
for the ordinal exponentiation of
to the power
and we define
If is a successor ordinal, then we define
to be the unique ordinal with
. We also define
if
is a limit ordinal. Similarly, if
, then we set
. Recall that every ordinal
has a unique
Cantor normal form
where ,
and
with
.
We define to be the class of positive numbers
of the form
for certain
subsets
and
of
with
. Numbers
in
are called monomials. It turns out
[11, Theorem 21] that the monomials form a subgroup of
and that there is a natural isomorphism between
and the ordered field
.
We will identify those two fields and thus see
as a field of well-based series. The ordinal
, seen as a surreal number, is the simplest element,
or
-minimum, of the class
.
In [4], we introduced the notion of surreal
substructures. A surreal substructure is a subclass of
such that
and
are isomorphic. The isomorphism
is unique and denoted by
.
Many important subclasses of
that are relevant
to the study of hyperserial properties of
are
surreal substructures. In particular, it is known that the following
classes are surreal substructures:
The classes ,
and
of positive, positive
infinite and infinitesimal numbers.
The classes and
of
monomials and infinite monomials.
The classes and
of
purely infinite and positive purely infinite numbers.
The class of log-atomic numbers.
If are surreal substructures, then the class
is a surreal substructure with
.
Given a subclass of
and
, we will write
so that and
.
We also write
and
.
If is a subclass of
and
are subsets of
with
, then the class
is called a cut in .
If
contains a unique simplest element, then we
denote this element by
and say that
is a cut representation (of
) in
.
These notations naturally extend to the case when
and
are subclasses of
with
.
A surreal substructure may be characterized as a
subclass of
such that for all cut
representations
in
,
the cut
has a unique simplest element [4,
Proposition 4.7].
Let be a surreal substructure. Note that we have
for all
.
Let
and let
be a cut
representation of
in
. Then
is cofinal with
respect to
in the sense that
has no strict upper bound in
and
has no strict lower bound in
[4, Proposition 4.11(b)].
Given numbers with
,
the number
is the unique
-maximal number with
.
We have
. Let
be a surreal substructure. Considering the isomorphism
, we see that for all
with
,
there is a unique
-maximal
element
of
with
, and we have
. In what follows, we will use this basic fact
several times without further mention.
Let be a subclass, let
be a surreal substructure and
be a function. Let
be functions defined for cut representations in
and such that
are
subsets of
whenever
is a
cut representation in
. We
say that
is a cut equation
for
if for all
,
we have
Elements in (resp.
)
are called left (resp. right)
options of this cut equation at
.
We say that the cut equation is uniform if we have
whenever is a cut representation in
. For instance, given
, consider the translation
on
. By [19,
Theorem 3.2], we have the following uniform cut equation for
on
:
![]() |
(3.1) |
We will need the following result from [4]:
be surreal substructures. Let
be a function from
to the class of subsets of
such that for
with
,
the set
is cofinal with respect to
. For
,
let
denote the class of elements
of
such that
and
are mutually cofinal. Let
be a cut equation on
that is extensive in the
sense that
Let be strictly increasing with cut equation
Then induces an embedding
for each element
of
.
One natural way to obtain surreal substructures is via convex
partitions. If is a surreal substructure, then a
convex partition of
is a
partition
of
whose
members are convex subclasses of
for the order
. We may then consider the
class
of simplest elements (i.e.
-minima) in each member of
. Those elements are said
-simple. For
, we let
denote the
unique member of
containing
. By [4, Proposition 4.16], the
class
contains a unique
-simple element, which we denote by
. The function
is a surjective
non-decreasing function
with
.
Given , note that we have
if and only if
.
For
, we write
. We have the following criterion to
characterize elements of
.
of
is
-simple
if and only if there is a cut representation
of
in
with
. Equivalently
is
-simple if and only if
.
We say that is thin if each
member of
has a cofinal and coinitial subset. We
then have:
is thin, then the class
is a surreal
substructure and
has the following uniform cut
equation:
A special type of thin convex partitions is that of partitions induced
by function groups acting on surreal substructures. A function
group on a surreal substructure
is a set-sized group of strictly increasing
bijections
under functional composition. We see
elements
of
as actions
on
and we sometimes write
and
instead of
and
, where
.
For such a function group ,
the collection
of classes
with is a thin convex partition of
. We write
.
We have the uniform cut equation
![]() |
(3.2) |
Consider sets of strictly increasing bijections
, then we say that
is pointwise cofinal with respect to
, and we write
,
if we have
. We also define
It is easy to see that is a function group on
and that we have
if
or
. The
relation
trivially implies
. If
and
, then we say that
and
are mutually pointwise cofinal and we
write
. We then have
.
We write (resp.
) if we have
(resp.
). We
also write
and
instead
of
and
.
Given a function group on
, the relation defined by
is
a partial order on
. We will
frequently rely on the basic fact that
is
partially bi-ordered in the sense that
Each of the examples of surreal substructures from Subsection 3.1
can be regarded as the classes for actions of
the following function groups
acting on
,
or
. For
and
, we define
Then we have the following list of correspondences :
The action of on
(resp.
)
yields
(resp.
), e.g.
.
The action of on
(resp.
)
yields
(resp.
).
The action of on
yields
.
The action of on
yields
.
The action of on
yields
(which will coincide with
).
Generalizations of those function groups will allow us to define certain
surreal substructures related to the hyperlogarithms and
hyperexponentials on .
In this section, we briefly recall the definition of hyperserial fields from [5] and how to construct such fields from their hyperserial skeletons.
Let be a formal, infinitely large indeterminate.
The field
of logarithmic
hyperseries of [14] is the smallest field
of well-based series that contains all ordinal real power products of
the hyperlogarithms
with
. It is naturally equipped with a derivation
and composition law
.
We define to be the ordered field of well-based
series
. If
are ordinals with
, then we
define
to be the subgroup of
of monomials
with
whenever
. As in [14],
we write
We have natural inclusions ,
hence natural inclusions
.
So for all
.
For
and
,
we will sometimes write
.
For , the map
is a strongly linear embedding [14, Lemma
6.6].
For and
,
we have
and
[14, Proposition 7.14].
For and successor ordinals
, we have
[14,
Lemma 5.6].
The same properties hold for the composition if
is replaced by
.
For
, the map
is injective, with image
[14,
Lemma 5.11]. For
, we define
to be the unique series in
with
.
Let be an ordered group. A real powering
operation on
is a law
of ordered -vector space on
. Let
be a field of well-based series with
,
let
, and let
be a function. For
, we define
to be the class of series
with
. We say that
is a hyperserial field if
for all
,
, and
.
for all
,
, and
with
.
for all ordinals
,
,
and
with
.
The map extends to a real powering
operation on
.
for all
.
for all
,
and
.
For each , we define the
function
. The
skeleton of
is defined to be
the structure
equipped with the real power
operation from HF5.
We say that is confluent if
for all
with
,
we have
In particular is a confluent hyperserial field.
It turns out that each hyperlogarithm on a
hyperserial field
can uniquely be reconstructed
from its restriction to the subset of
-atomic
hyperseries (here we say that
is
-atomic if
for all
). One of the main ideas
behind [14] is to turn this fact into a way to
construct hyperserial fields. This leads to the definition of a
hyperserial skeleton as a field
with partially
defined hyperlogarithms
,
which satisfy suitable counterparts of the above axioms HF1
until HF7.
More precisely, let be a field of well-based
series and fix
. A
hyperserial skeleton on
of
force
consists of a family of partial
functions
for
, called (hyper)logarithms, which satisfy a
list of axioms that we will describe now.
First of all, the domains on which
the partial functions
are defined should satisfy
the following axioms:
It will be convenient to also define the class
by
Consider an ordinal written in Cantor normal
form
where
and
. We denote by
the partial function
It follows from the definition that for all , the class
consists of
those series
for which
and
for all
.
We call such series
-atomic.
Secondly, the hyperlogarithms with
should satisfy the following axioms:
Axioms for the logarithm Functional equation: Asymptotics: Monotonicity: Regularity: Surjective logarithm: |
Axioms for the hyperlogarithms (for each |
Finally, for with
,
we also need the following axiom
Note that and
together imply
,
whence
automatically holds. This will in
particular be the case for
(see Section 5).
In summary, we have:
,
we say that
is a hyperserial
skeleton of force
if it
satisfies
,
,
,
, and
for all
, as well as
for all ordinals
.
Assume that is a hyperserial skeleton of force
. The partial logarithm
extends naturally into a strictly increasing morphism
, which we call the
logarithm and denote by
or
[5, Section 4.1]. If
satisfies
, then this extended
logarithm is actually an isomorphism [29, Proposition
2.3.8]. In that case, for any
and
, we define
.
of force
and
, we inductively define the notion of
-confluence in conjunction with the definition of functions
, as follows.
The field is said
-confluent if
is
non-trivial. The function
maps every
positive infinite series
onto its dominant
monomial
. For each
, we write
Let be such that
is
-confluent for all
and let
.
If is a successor ordinal, then we write
for the class of series
with
for a certain .
If is a limit ordinal, then we write
for the class of series
with
for a certain .
We say that is
-confluent if each class
contains a
-atomic
element; we then define
to be this
element.
This inductive definition is sound. Indeed, if
and
is
-confluent
for all
, then the functions
with
are well-defined
and non-decreasing. Thus, for
,
the collection of
with
forms a partition of
into convex subclasses.
We say that is confluent if it is
-confluent. If
has force
, then we say that
is
-confluent,
or confluent, if
is
-confluent for all
.
is a confluent
hyperserial skeleton, then there is a unique function
with
such that is a confluent hyperserial
field.
Assume now that is only a hyperserial skeleton
of force
and that
is an
ordinal with
such that
is
-confluent. Let
. By [5, Definition
4.11 and Lemma 4.12], the partial function
naturally extends into a function
that we still
denote by
. This extended
function is strictly increasing, by‘ [5, Corollary
4.17]. If
is a successor ordinal, then it
satisfies the functional equation
![]() |
(4.2) |
by [5, Proposition 4.13]. For ,
we have a strictly increasing function
obtained
as a composition of functions
with
, as in (4.1). By [5,
Proposition 4.7], we have
In a traditional transseries field ,
the transmonomials are characterized by the fact that, for any
, we have
In particular, the logarithm is surjective as
soon as
is defined for all
with
. In hyperserial fields,
similar properties hold for
-atomic
elements with respect to the hyperexponential
, as we will recall now.
Given , let
be a confluent hyperserial skeleton
of force
. By [5, Theorem
4.1], we have a composition
.
Given
, the extended function
is strictly increasing and hence injective.
Consequently,
has a partially defined functional
inverse that we denote by
.
The characterization (4.3) generalizes as follows:
is
-truncated if
Given , we say that a
series
is
-truncated if
For any , we write
for the class of
-truncated series in
.
and
, we have
In general, we have .
Whenever
is a successor ordinal, we even have
Let be a series such that
is defined. By [5, Lemma 7.14], the series
is
-truncated if and only if
For , the axiom
is therefore equivalent to the inclusion
. For
,
there is a unique
-maximal
truncation
of
which is
-truncated. By [5,
Propositions 6.16 and 6.17], the classes
with form a partition of
into convex subclasses. Moreover, the series
is both the unique
-truncated
element and the
-minimum of
. If
is defined, then we have the following simplified definition [5,
Proposition 7.19] of the class
:
The following shows that the existence of on
is essentially equivalent to its existence on
.
and assume
that for
, the function
is defined on
.
Then each hyperlogarithm
for
is bijective.
If Proposition 4.6 holds, then we say that
is a (confluent) hyperserial field of force
. Since every function
is then a
strictly increasing bijection
,
we obtain
for each ordinal with
. By [5, Corollary 7.23], for all
, we have
Recall that is identified with the ordered field
of well-based series
. In
this section, we describe, in the first level
of
our hierarchy, the properties of
equipped with
the Kruskal-Gonshor logarithm.
In [19, Chapter 10], Gonshor defines the exponential
function , relying on partial
Taylor sums of the real exponential function. For
and
, write
We then have the recursive definition
We will sometimes write instead of
. The function
is a
bijective morphism [19, Corollary 10.1, Corollary 10.3],
which satisfies:
We define to be the functional inverse of
, and we set
. Given an ordinal
,
we understand that
still stands for the
-th ordinal power of
from section 2.2.2 and warn the reader that
does not necessarily coincide with
.
Together, the above facts imply that satisfies
the axioms
,
,
,
and
.
Therefore,
is a hyperserial skeleton of force
. The extension of
to
from section 4.5
coincides with
. It was shown
in [13] that
is an elementary
extension of
. See [28,
7, 8] for more details on
and
.
Berarducci and Mantova identified the class of
-atomic numbers as
[9, Corollary 5.17] and showed that
is
-confluent
[9, Corollary 5.11]. Thus
is a
confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
.
Thanks to [5, Theorem 1.1], it is therefore equipped with a
composition law
. See [29, 10] for further details on extensions of this
composition law to exponential extensions of
.
Berarducci and Mantova also proved [9, Theorem 8.10] that
is a field of transseries in the sense of [24, 29], i.e. that
satisfies the axiom
of [29,
Definition 2.2.1]. We plan to prove in subsequent work that
satisfies a generalized version of
.
We have seen in section 5 that is a
confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
for
. The aim of this section is
to extend this result to any ordinal
.
More precisely, we will define a sequence
of
partial functions on
such that for each ordinal
, the structure
is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
, and
coincides with
Gonshor's logarithm.
Assume for the moment that we can define and
as bijective strictly increasing functions on
for all ordinals
.
This is the case already for
.
Let us introduce several useful groups that act on
, as well as several remarkable subclasses of
.
Given an ordinal , we write
and we consider the function groups
where ,
and
act on
.
We also define
We write and
for each
. In the case when
, note that
By Proposition 3.3 and the fact the set-sized function
groups ,
,
,
and
induce thin partitions of
, we may define the following surreal
substructures
Here we note that corresponds to the class
of infinite monomials in
and
maps positive infinite numbers to their dominant
monomial. Similarly,
coincides with
and
maps
to
. In sections 6
and 7, we will prove the following identities.
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
The first and third identities imply in particular that the classes and
from section 4
are in fact surreal substructures, when regarding
as a hyperserial field.
For the definition of the partial hyperlogarithm , we will proceed by induction on
. Let
be an ordinal.
Until the end of this section we make the following induction
hypotheses:
Induction hypotheses
|
These induction hypotheses require a few additional explanations.
Assuming that holds, the partial
functions
with
extend
into strictly increasing bijections
,
by the results from section 4. Using (1.3),
this allows us to define a strictly increasing bijection
for any
and we denote by
its functional inverse. In particular, this ensures that
the hypotheses
and
make sense.
Remark for
are always defined
by (6.1) below. In particular, our construction of
is not relative to any potential
construction of the preceding hyperlogarithms
with
that would satify the induction hypotheses
,
,
and
. Instead, we define
one specific family of functions
that
satisfy our requirements, as well as the additional identities listed in
subsection 6.1.
,
and
hold for
.
be a limit ordinal and assume that
,
, and
hold for all
. Then
,
, and
hold.
follows immediately by induction. Towards
,
note that we have
by
(and thus
) and
for all
. By
[4, Proposition 6.28], we have
. So
holds.
From now on, we assume that ,
, and
are satisfied for
and we define
The remainder of the section is dedicated to the definition of and the proof of the inductive hypotheses
I
,
I
, and
I
for
. In combination with Propositions 6.2
and 6.3, this will complete our induction and the proof of
Theorem 1.1.
Recall that we have by
.
In particular
is a surreal substructure.
Consider
. The skeleton
is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
by
. So for
, (4.7) and
yield
.
In view of and
, the simplest way to define
is
via the cut equation:
![]() |
(6.1) |
Note the asymmetry between left and right options
and
(instead of
)
for generic
and
.
In Corollary 7.4 below, we will derive a more symmetric but
equivalent cut equation for
,
as promised in the introduction. For now, we prove that (6.1)
is warranted and that
,
, and
hold.
is well-defined on
and, for
, we have
.
. Let
such that
holds for all
.
Let
and
.
We have
or
,
so
or
yields
For , we have
and
, whence
for all . Hence,
We clearly have . Finally,
so . This shows that
is defined and
Since , it follows that
holds.
holds.
holds.
and write
. Let
with
. We have
and
so
.
Moreover
is positive infinite. The number
is strictly simpler than
, so
does not lie in the cut
which defines
in (6.1). Therefore,
there is an
or an
and an
ordinal
with
or
. Consider the first case. We have
for a certain
.
So
and
is a successor ordinal, then the cut equation
be a cut
representation in
and write
. For
,
we have
so
.
For
, we have
by
. Since
, it follows that
. We may thus define the number
In order to show that (6.1) is uniform, we need to prove
that , for any choice of the
cut representation
. We will
do so by proving that
and
.
Recall that is cofinal with respect to
and that
is strictly increasing.
Consequently, we have
Given , there is an
with
. By
, we have
for
all
, so
. This proves that
lies
in the cut defining
as per (6.1),
whence
.
Conversely, in order to prove that ,
it suffices to show that
lies in the cut
Let and let
be
-maximal with
. We have
,
whence
, by
. If
,
then
, so
yields
and
.
Otherwise
, so
yields
. This
proves that
.
In this subsection we derive , under
the assumption that
is a successor ordinal. We
start with the following inequality.
, then we have
on
.
,
there are
and
with
. We have
on by (4.2). Note that
, so
yields
Let . Since
is a surreal substructure, we may consider the
-atomic number
We claim that . Assume that
and write
.
We have
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
Assume now that . The
function
is strictly increasing with
. Therefore
so . Since
, the cut equation (6.1) for
yields
Given , we have
and
. We deduce
that
Moreover, by definition, we have
so . Symmetric arguments
yield
. Lemma 6.9
implies that
, whence
. We get
, whence
.
Thus
lies in the cut defining
in (6.2), so
.
This proves our claim that
![]() |
(6.3) |
, we have
.
. Let
be such that the
result holds on
. By (6.3), we have
Let and
range in
and
respectively. Proposition
6.8 and our induction hypothesis yield:
On the other hand, we have
Combining our results so far, we have proved that
is a hyperserial skeleton of force
.
We next prove that is
-confluent.
is a non-zero limit ordinal, then the function
groups
and
are mutually
pointwise cofinal. In particular, we have
and
.
and
, we have
since
. We have
Therefore . For
, there is
with
. By (4.2), we have
, any
-minimal element of
is
-atomic.
denote the
class of numbers
that are
-minimal in
.
Any such
-minimal number
is also
-minimal
in
, hence
-atomic. Thus
is
defined on
. It is enough to
prove that
is closed under
in order to obtain that
.
Consider , and recall that we
have
Assume for contradiction that is not
-minimal in
. So there is a
with
. This implies that
lies outside the cut defining
, so
is larger than a right
option of (6.4) or smaller than a left option of (6.4).
Assume first that . So there
is an
with
.
We have
so there is an
with
Thus
This contradicts the -minimality
of
.
Now consider the other case when .
In particular,
must be larger than a right
option of (6.4). Symmetric arguments imply that we cannot
have
for some
.
So there must exist a
with
. If
is a limit
ordinal, then
so Lemma 6.11 yields
, whence
. If
is a successor
ordinal, then there is a
with
, so
and Proposition 6.10 yields .
In both cases, we thus have
.
For any integer
, we deduce
that
This contradicts the fact that lies in
.
is
-confluent.
The corollary implies that is a confluent
hyperserial skeleton of force
.
Moreover, the class
is that of
-minima and thus
-minima
in the convex classes
for . In other words, we have
. In order to conclude that
is a surreal substructure, we still need to
prove that the convex partition
is thin. This
will be done at the end of section 6.6 below.
be a cut
representation in
and write
. We have
By (4.6), this shows that
In particular, the number
We have shown that is a hyperserial skeleton of
force
. In order to prove
that
has force
,
it remains to prove that every
-truncated
number
has a hyperexponential
. This is the purpose of this subsection.
, and
has the following cut equation on
:
![]() |
(6.5) |
. Let
such
that
is defined on
with
the given equation. We will first show that the number
is well-defined. We will then prove that .
Let and
.
If
, then
by the definition of
. So
. Otherwise, we have
, whence
by
definition of
, so
. So we always have
We also have , so
. This proves that
. It remains to show that
Note that , so by the
definition of
, we have
![]() |
(6.7) |
Hence , which completes the
proof that
is well-defined.
Let us now prove that . Note
that
by Proposition 3.2. First
assume that
is a limit ordinal. Lemma 6.11
yields
, so we may write
By (4.6), for the classes that
and
are mutually cofinal and
coinitial. Moreover, we have
for all
, by our hypothesis on
. Hence, Proposition 6.14 and (4.6) imply
Note that , so
. Now
.
We also have
where
So . Since
, the inequality
follows from Proposition 3.2. Finally, we have by
definition that
, so
. This proves that
, so
.
Assume now that is a successor ordinal. For all
, the sets
,
,
and
are mutually cofinal. So we can rewrite (6.6) as
As in the limit case, Proposition 6.14 yields
Let . There is an
with
. Since
, we have
In particular . We saw in (6.7) that
, whence
. We also obtain the
inequalities
in a similar way as in the limit case.
With Proposition 6.15, we have completed the proof of . By (4.7), we have
for all
.
Given
, we also deduce from
(4.6) that the set
is cofinal and
coinitial in
. The convex
partition defined by
is thus thin. By
Proposition 3.3, the class
is a
surreal substructure with uniform cut equation
![]() |
(6.8) |
For , we have
, so
.
We deduce that the following equivalent is equivalent to (6.8):
We now prove ,
and Theorem 1.1.
is a limit ordinal, then we have
on
.
.
We have
, so (4.8)
yields
with
and
, we have
on
, i.e.
holds.
. Write
and
where
and
.
We have
is the class of
-atomic
numbers, i.e.
holds.
.
By Corollary 6.13, the simplest element of
is
-atomic. Since
, we deduce that
.
In particular, the class is a surreal
substructure. We have proved
,
and
, so we obtain the
following by induction:
is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
.
Combining this with Propositions 4.3 and 4.6,
we obtain Theorem 1.1. Let us finally show that contains only one
-atomic
element.
is the only
-atomic
element in
. For all
, there is
with
.
In this section, we give various identities regarding the function
groups introduced in Section 6.1. In what follows, is a non-zero ordinal and
.
Given , let
if
is a successor ordinal and
if
is a limit ordinal. In this subsection, we
will derive the following simplified cut equations for
on
and
on
:
For all , the set
contains only
-atomic
numbers, so (7.3) is indeed a cut equation of the form
.
Remark instead of
in (7.2)
and the (related) absence of the left option
in
(7.4). So (7.2) and (7.4) give
lighter sets of conditions than those in (6.1) and (6.5) to define
and
. This seemingly meager simplification will be
crucial in further work. Indeed, combined with Proposition 3.1,
this allows one to determine large classes of numbers
with
.
First note that the cut equations (7.1) and (7.3)
if they hold are uniform (see [6, Remark 1]). Moreover, we
claim that (7.1,7.2) are
equivalent and that (7.3,7.4)
are equivalent. Indeed, recall that for a thin convex partition of a surreal substructure
and
any cut representation
in
, one has
For and
the classes
and
are mutually cofinal by
(4.6). Similarly,
and
are mutually coinitial. By Lemma 6.11, the
classes
and
are mutually
cofinal. So it is enough to prove that (7.1) and (7.3)
are valid cut equations for
and
respectively.
is a successor ordinal, then the identities (7.1)
and (7.3) hold.
and set
We have so in view of (6.1), it is
enough to prove that
to conclude that
. Let
.
If
, then the inequality
entails
whence
and
.
Otherwise, we have
, so
, and
.
It is enough to prove that
.
Recall that
by (3.1). We see that for all
. We have
so
. Thus
. So (7.1) holds.
Now let and set
By uniformity of (7.1), we have
We now assume that is a limit ordinal. For
, define
, we have
. Let
be
such that (7.5), (7.6), (7.7) and
(7.8) hold for all
with
.
For and
,
we have
. We have
by definition of
if
and by definition of
if
. This proves that
is defined.
Let and
.
If
, then we have
by definition of
.
Since
and
,
we have
for all
We
deduce that
. If
, then
by definition of
. Since
, we obtain
.
This proves that
is defined.
Since (7.7) and (7.8) hold on , we have
By (6.9), this yields ,
so (7.7) holds for
.
From (7.7), we get .
By Proposition 6.14 and our assumption that (7.8)
holds on
, we have
, set
, and we show that
. Since (7.3) is uniform, we have
Remark can be viewed as alternative definitions for
those functions, since they hold inductively on their domain of
definition. It is unclear how to develop our theory directly upon these
alternative definitions. In particular, does there exists a direct way
to see that the cut equation (7.2) is warranted, and that
the corresponding function satisfies
and
?
as in Section 6.1, we have
.
Assume that is a successor ordinal. Then we have
by (4.4), so the functions
and
are both strictly
increasing bijections from
onto
.
is a successor ordinal. Then for
, we have
on
.
. We prove the lemma by induction on
. Let
with
whenever is strictly simpler than
. We let
denote generic
elements of
and we note that
. By (6.8), we have
Recall that is a successor ordinal. Since (4.2) holds for all
,
the sets
and
are
mutually cofinal and coinitial. Moreover
for all
and
,
so
By (3.1), we have
The numbers and
are
-truncated so
lies in the cut
is a successor ordinal, then we have
on
.
Consequently,
.
is
pointwise cofinal in
. So
is pointwise cofinal in
. For
,
there is
such that
.
We have
is a successor ordinal, then for
we have
. Let
be
such that the relation holds on
.
By (6.3), we have
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
|
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
||
![]() |
![]() |
Noting that on
,
the previous relation further generalizes as follows.
is a successor ordinal and let
. Then
be such that
for all strictly simpler with respect to the
product order
. For
, let
be
the function
on
and let
. By (3.1) and
(3.2), we have
By (7.1), Lemma 7.7 and (3.1), we have:
We deduce that
It is enough to prove that to conclude that
. Towards this, fix an
with
.
Lemma 7.9 yields
Remark , we have
,
and
. Therefore we can see
as a system of fractional and real iterates of
the hyperexponential function
on
. The previous proposition shows that the
action of those iterates on
-atomic
numbers reduces to translations, modulo the parametrization
. In particular, one can compute the functional
square root of
on
in
terms of sign sequences using the material from [3].
is a successor ordinal, then
.
,
we have
. By Lemma 7.9,
it follows that
. This
implies that
, so
is
-simple.
.
So
. By Proposition 3.1,
the number
is simplest in
is a successor ordinal, then
.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. On numbers, germs, and transseries. In Proc. Int. Cong. of Math. 2018, volume 1, pages 1–24. Rio de Janeiro, 2018.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der
Hoeven. The surreal numbers as a universal -field. J. Eur. Math. Soc.,
21(4):1179–1199, 2019.
V. Bagayoko. Sign sequences of log-atomic numbers. Hal-02952455, 2020.
V. Bagayoko and J. van der Hoeven. Surreal substructures. HAL-02151377 (pre-print), 2019.
V. Bagayoko, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Hyperserial fields. (notes non publiées), 2020.
V. Bagayoko, J. van der Hoeven, and V. Mantova. Defining a surreal hyperexponential. HAL-02861485 (pre-print), 2020.
A. Berarducci. Surreal numbers, exponentiation and derivations. https://arxiv.org/abs/2008.06878, 08 2020.
A. Berarducci, S. Kuhlmann, V. Mantova, and M. Matusinski. Exponential fields and Conway's omega-map. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 2019.
A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Surreal numbers, derivations and transseries. JEMS, 20(2):339–390, 2018.
A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Transseries as germs of surreal functions. Trans. of the AMS, 371:3549–3592, 2019.
B. I. Dahn and P. Göring. Notes on exponential-logarithmic terms. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 127:45–50, 1986.
L. van den Dries and Ph. Ehrlich. Fields of surreal numbers and exponentiation. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 167(2):173–188, 2001.
L. van den Dries, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Logarithmic hyperseries. Trans. of the AMS, 372(7):5199–5241, 2019.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Sur la grandeur relative des infinis des fonctions. Annali di Matematica Pura ed Applicata (1867-1897), 4(1):338–353, 1870.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über asymptotische Werte, infinitäre Approximationen und infinitäre Auflösung von Gleichungen. Math. Ann., 8:363–414, 1875.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über die Paradoxen des Infinitärscalcüls. Math. Ann., 11:149–167, 1877.
J. Écalle. Introduction aux fonctions analysables et preuve constructive de la conjecture de Dulac. Hermann, collection: Actualités mathématiques, 1992.
H. Gonshor. An Introduction to the Theory of Surreal Numbers. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1986.
H. Hahn. Über die nichtarchimedischen Größensysteme. Sitz. Akad. Wiss. Wien, 116:601–655, 1907.
G. H. Hardy. Orders of infinity. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1910.
G. H. Hardy. Properties of logarithmico-exponential functions. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 10(2):54–90, 1911.
D. Harvey and J. van der Hoeven. Faster polynomial multiplication over finite fields using cyclotomic coefficient rings. Accepted for publication in J. of Complexity, 2019.
J. van der Hoeven. Automatic asymptotics. PhD thesis, École polytechnique, Palaiseau, France, 1997.
J. van der Hoeven. Transséries fortement monotones. Chapter 1 of unpublished CNRS activity report, https://www.texmacs.org/joris/schmeling/rap1-2000.pdf, 2000.
J. van der Hoeven. Transseries and real differential algebra, volume 1888 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, 2006.
J. van der Hoeven. The Jolly Writer. Your Guide to GNU TeXmacs. Scypress, 2020.
V. Mantova and M. Matusinski. Surreal numbers with derivation, Hardy fields and transseries: a survey. Contemporary Mathematics, pages 265–290, 2017.
M. C. Schmeling. Corps de transséries. PhD thesis, Université Paris-VII, 2001.
simplest number between
and
4
field of well-based series with real
coefficients over
5
support of a series 5
truncation
of
5
and
5
series
with
5
series
with
5
series
with
and
5
class of ordinals 6
simplicity relation 6
ordinal exponentiation with base
at
6
if
is a successor ordinal and
if
is a limit ordinal 6
for
6
the surreal substructure
7
class of
-simple
elements 8
projection
8
class of numbers
with
8
comparison between sets of strictly
increasing bijections 9
function group generated by
9
and
are mutually pointwise cofinal 9
translation
9
homothety
9
power function
9
function group
9
function group
9
function group
9
function group
9
function group
9
field of logarithmic hyperseries 10
group of logarithmic hypermonomials of force
10
field of logarithmic hyperseries of force
10
unique series in
with
10
hyperlogarithm function
11
class of
-atomic
series 11
functional equation 12
asymptotics axiom 12
monotonicity axiom 12
regularity axiom 12
infinite products axiom
12
class of series
with
13
-atomic
element of
13
hyperexponential function
14
class of
-truncated
series 14
series
with
14
-maximal
-truncated truncation of
14
function group
16
function group
16
function group
16
function group
16
structure of
-simple
elements 16
structure of
-simple
elements 16
structure of
-simple
elements 16
structure of
-simple
elements 16