|
Surreal numbers form the ultimate extension of the field of real
numbers with infinitely large and small quantities and in
particular with all ordinal numbers. Hyperseries can be regarded
as the ultimate formal device for representing regular growth
rates at infinity. In this paper, we show that any surreal number
can naturally be regarded as the value of a hyperseries at the
first infinite ordinal |
At the end of the 19-th century, two theories emerged for computations with infinitely large quantities. The first one was due to du Bois-Reymond [19, 20, 21], who developed a “calculus of infinities” to deal with the growth rates of functions in one real variable at infinity. The second theory of “ordinal numbers” was proposed by Cantor [13] as a way to count beyond the natural numbers and to describe the sizes of sets in his recently introduced set theory.
Du Bois-Reymond's original theory was partly informal and not to the
taste of Cantor, who misunderstood it [25]. The theory was
firmly grounded and further developed by Hausdorff and Hardy. Hausdorff
formalized du Bois-Reymond's “orders of infinity” in
Cantor's set-theoretic universe [24]. Hardy focused on the
computational aspects and introduced the differential field of
logarithmico-exponential functions [28, 29]:
such a function is constructed from the real numbers and an
indeterminate (that we think of as tending to
infinity) using the field operations, exponentiation, and the logarithm.
Subsequently, this led to the notion of a Hardy field [12].
As to Cantor's theory of ordinal numbers, Conway proposed a dramatic
generalization in the 1970s. Originally motivated by game theory, he
introduced the proper class of surreal
numbers [14], which simultaneously contains the set
of all real numbers and the class
of all ordinals. This class comes with a natural ordering
and arithmetic operations that turn
into a
non-Archimedean real closed field. In particular,
,
,
,
are all
surreal numbers, where
stands for the first
infinite ordinal.
Conway's original definition of surreal numbers is somewhat informal and draws inspiration from both Dedekind cuts and von Neumann's construction of the ordinals:
“If and
are
any two sets of (surreal) numbers, and no member of
is
any member of
, then there is a (surreal) number
. All (surreal) numbers are constructed in
this way.”
The notation is called Conway's
bracket. Conway proposed to consider
as the
simplest number between
and
. Indeed, it turns out that one may
define a partial ordering
on
with
for any number
with
. This so-called
simplicity relation has the additional property that any
can be written canonically as
One may regard as the set of surreal numbers
that were defined before
when using Conway's
recursive definition. Conway's bracket is uniquely determined by the
simplicity relation
and vice versa.
The ring operations on are defined in a
recursive way that is both very concise and intuitive: given
and
, we define
It is quite amazing that these definitions coincide with the traditional
definitions when and
are
real, but that they also work for the ordinal numbers and beyond.
Subsequently, Gonshor also showed how to extend the real exponential
function to
[26] and this extension
preserves all first order properties of
[16]. Simpler accounts and definitions of
can be found in [37, 9].
The theory of Hardy fields focuses on the study of growth properties of germs of actual real differentiable functions at infinity. An analogue formal theory arose after the introduction of transseries by Dahn and Göring [15] and, independently, by Écalle [22, 23]. Transseries are a natural generalization of the above definition of Hardy's logarithmico-exponential functions, by also allowing for infinite sums (modulo suitable precautions to ensure that such sums make sense). One example of a transseries is
In particular, any transseries can be written as a generalized series
with real coefficients
and whose (trans)monomials
are exponentials of
other (generally “simpler”) transseries. The support
of such a series should be well based in the
sense that it should be well ordered for the opposite ordering of the
natural ordering
on the group of transmonomials
. The precise definition of a
transseries depends on further technical requirements on the allowed
supports. But for all reasonable choices, “the” resulting
field
of transseries possesses a lot of closure
properties: it is ordered and closed under derivation, composition,
integration, and functional inversion [22, 30,
18]; it also satisfies an intermediate value property for
differential polynomials [32, 3].
It turns out that surreal numbers and transseries are similar in many
respects: both and
are
real closed fields that are closed under exponentiation and taking
logarithms of positive elements. Surreal numbers too can be represented
uniquely as Hahn series
with real coefficients
and monomials in a suitable multiplicative
subgroup
of
.
Any transseries
actually naturally induces a
surreal number
by substituting
for
and the map
is
injective [11].
But there are also differences. Most importantly, elements of can be regarded as functions that can be derived and
composed. Conversely, the surreal numbers
come
equipped with the Conway bracket. In fact, it would be nice if any
surreal number could naturally be regarded as the value
of a unique transseries
at
. Indeed, this would allow us to transport the
functional structure of
to the surreal numbers.
Conversely, we might equip the transseries with a Conway bracket and
other exotic operations on the surreal numbers. The second author
conjectured the existence of such a correspondence between
and a suitably generalized field of the transseries [32, page 16]; see also [2] for a more recent
account.
Now we already observed that at least some surreal numbers can be written uniquely as
for some transseries
. Which
numbers and what kind of functions do we miss? Since a perfect
correspondence would induce a Conway bracket on
, it is instructive to consider subsets
with
and examine which natural
growth orders might fit between
and
.
One obvious problem with ordinary transseries is that there exists no
transseries that grows faster than any iterated exponential . Consequently, there exists no transseries
with
.
A natural candidate for a function that grows faster than any iterated
exponential is the first hyperexponential
, which satisfies the functional equation
It was shown by Kneser [33] that this equation actually has
a real analytic solution on .
A natural hyperexponential
on
was constructed more recently in [8]. In particular,
.
More generally, one can formally introduce the transfinite sequence of hyperexponentials of arbitrary strengths
, together with the sequence
of their functional inverses, called
hyperlogarithms. Each
with
satisfies the equation
and there again exist real analytic solutions to this equation [38].
The function does not satisfy any natural
functional equation, but we have the following infinite product formula
for the derivative of every hyperlogarithm
:
We showed in [6] how to define and
for any
and
.
The traditional field of transseries is not
closed under hyperexponentials and hyperlogarithms, but it is possible
to define generalized fields of hyperseries that do enjoy this
additional closure property. Hyperserial grow rates were studied from a
formal point of view in [22, 23]. The first
systematic construction of hyperserial fields of strength
is due to Schmeling [38]. In this paper, we
will rely on the more recent constructions from [17, 7] that are fully general. In particular, the surreal numbers
form a hyperserial field in the sense of [7], when equipped with the hyperexponentials and
hyperlogarithms from [6].
A less obvious problematic cut in the field of
transseries
arises by taking
Here again, there exists no transseries with
. This cut has actually a
natural origin, since any “tame” solution of the functional
equation
![]() |
(1.1) |
lies in this cut. What is missing here is a suitable notion of “nested transseries” that encompasses expressions like
![]() |
(1.2) |
This type of cuts were first considered in [30, Section 2.7.1]. Subsequently, the second author and his former PhD student Schmeling developed an abstract notion of generalized fields of transseries [31, 38] that may contain nested transseries. However, it turns out that expressions like (1.2) are ambiguous: one may construct fields of transseries that contain arbitrarily large sets of pairwise distinct solutions to (1.1).
In order to investigate this ambiguity more closely, let us turn to the
surreal numbers. The above cut induces a cut
in
.
Nested transseries solutions
to the functional
equation (1.1) should then give rise to surreal numbers
with
and such that
are all monomials in
.
In [5, Section 8], we showed that those numbers
actually form a class
that is
naturally parameterized by a surreal number (
forms a so-called surreal substructure). Here we note that
analogue results hold when replacing Gonshor's exponentiation by
Conway's
-map
(which generalizes Cantor's
-map
when
). This was already
noted by Conway himself [14, pages 34–36] and further
worked out by Lemire [34, 35, 36].
Section 6 of the present paper will be devoted to
generalizing the result from [5, Section 8] to nested
hyperseries.
Besides the two above types of superexponential and nested cuts, no
other examples of “cuts that cannot be filled” come
naturally to our mind. This led the second author to conjecture [32, page 16] that there exists a field
of suitably generalized hyperseries in
such that
each surreal number can uniquely be represented as the value
of a hyperseries
at
. In order to prove this conjecture, quite some
machinery has been developed since: a systematic theory of surreal
substructures [5], sufficiently general notions of
hyperserial fields [17, 7], and definitions of
on the surreals that give
the structure of a hyperserial field [8, 6].
Now one characteristic property of generalized hyperseries in should be that they can uniquely be described using
suitable expressions that involve
,
real numbers, infinite summation, hyperlogarithms, hyperexponentials,
and a way to disambiguate nested expansions. The main goal of this paper
is to show that any surreal number can indeed be described uniquely by a
hyperserial expression of this kind in
.
This essentially solves the conjecture from [32, page 16]
by thinking of hyperseries in
as surreal numbers
in which we replaced
by
. Of course, it remains desirable to give a formal
construction of
that does not involve surreal
numbers and to specify the precise kind of properties that our
“suitably generalized” hyperseries should possess. We intend
to address this issue in a forthcoming paper.
Other work in progress concerns the definition of a derivation and a
composition on . Now
Berarducci and Mantova showed how to define a derivation on
that is compatible with infinite summation and
exponentiation [10]. In [4, 1],
it was shown that there actually exist many such derivations and that
they all satisfy the same first order theory as the ordered differential
field
. However, as pointed
out in [2], Berarducci and Mantova's derivation does not
obey the chain rule with respect to
.
The hyperserial derivation that we propose to construct should not have
this deficiency and therefore be a better candidate for the
derivation on
with respect to
.
In this paper, we will strongly rely on previous work from [5, 17, 7, 8, 6]. The main results from these previous papers will be recalled in Sections 2, 3, and 4. For the sake of this introduction, we start with a few brief reminders.
The field of logarithmic hyperseries
was defined and studied in [17]. It is a field of Hahn
series
in the sense of [27] that is
equipped with a logarithm
, a
derivation
, and a
composition
. Moreover, for
each ordinal
, it contains an
element
such that
for all and all ordinals
. Moreover, if the Cantor normal form of
is given by
with
, then we have
The derivation and composition on satisfy the
usual rules of calculus and in particular a formal version of Taylor
series expansions.
In [7], Kaplan and the authors defined the concept of a
hyperserial field to be a field of Hahn
series with a logarithm
and a composition law
, such that various natural
compatibility requirements are satisfied. For every ordinal
, we then define the hyperlogarithm
of strength
by
. We showed in [6] how
to define bijective hyperlogarithms
for which
has the structure of a hyperserial field. For
every ordinal
, the
functional inverse
of
is
called the hyperexponential of strength
.
The main aim of this paper is to show that any surreal number is not just an abstract hyperseries in the sense of [6], but that we can regard it as a hyperseries in
. We will do this by constructing a suitable
unambiguous description of
in terms of
, the real numbers, infinite
summation, the hyperexponentials, and the hyperlogarithms.
If for some ordinary transseries
, then the idea would be to expand
as a linear combination of monomials, then to rewrite
every monomial as an exponential of a transseries, and finally to
recursively expand these new transseries. This process stops whenever we
hit an iterated logarithm of
.
In fact, this transserial expansion process works for any surreal number
. However, besides the
iterated logarithms (and exponentials) of
,
there exist other monomials
such that
is a monomial for all
.
Such monomials are said to be log-atomic. More generally, given
, we say that
is
-atomic
if
for all
.
We write
for the set of such numbers. If we wish
to further expand an
-atomic
monomial
as a hyperseries, then it is natural to
pick
such that
is not
-atomic, to recursively
expand
, and then to write
.
Unfortunately, the above idea is slightly too simple to be useful. In
order to expand monomials as hyperseries, we need something more
technical. In Section 5, we show that every non-trivial
monomial has a unique expansion of exactly one
of the two following forms:
![]() |
(1.3) |
where ,
, and
,
with
; or
![]() |
(1.4) |
where ,
,
with
,
,
and where
lies in
.
Moreover, if
then it is imposed that
,
,
and that
cannot be written as
where
,
,
,
and
.
After expanding in the above way, we may pursue
with the recursive expansions of
and
as hyperseries. Our next objective is to investigate the
shape of the recursive expansions that arise by doing so. Indeed,
already in the case of ordinary transseries, such recursive expansions
may give rise to nested expansions like
![]() |
(1.5) |
One may wonder whether it is also possible to obtain expansions like
![]() |
(1.6) |
Expansions of the forms (1.5) and (1.6) are
said to be well-nested and ill-nested, respectively.
The axiom T4 for fields of transseries in [38]
prohibits the existence of ill-nested expansions. It was shown in [10] that satisfies this axiom
T4.
The definition of hyperserial fields in [6] does not contain a counterpart for the axiom T4. The main goal of section 4 is to generalize this property to hyperserial fields and prove the following theorem:
Now there exist surreal numbers for which the above recursive expansion
process leads to a nested expansion of the form (1.5). In
[5, Section 8], we proved that the class
of such numbers actually forms a surreal substructure. This
means that
is isomorphic to
for the restriction
of
to
. In particular, although
the nested expansion (1.5) is inherently ambiguous,
elements in
are naturally parameterized by
surreal numbers in
.
The main goal of Section 6 is to prove a hyperserial
analogue of the result from [5, Section 8]. Now the
expansion (1.5) can be described in terms of the sequence
. More generally, in Section
6 we the define the notion of a nested sequence in
order to describe arbitrary nested hyperserial expansions. Our main
result is the following:
In Section 7, we reach the main goal of this paper, which
is to uniquely describe any surreal number as a generalized hyperseries
in . This goal can be split
up into two tasks. First of all, we need to specify the hyperserial
expansion process that we informally described above and show that it
indeed leads to a hyperserial expansion in
,
for any surreal number. This will be done in Section 7.2,
where we will use labeled trees in order to represent hyperserial
expansions. Secondly, these trees may contain infinite branches (also
called paths) that correspond to nested numbers in the sense of Section
6. By Theorem 1.2, any such nested number can
uniquely be identified using a surreal parameter. By associating a
surreal number to each infinite branch, this allows us to construct a
unique hyperserial description in
for
any surreal number and prove our main result:
Let be a totally ordered (and possibly
class-sized) abelian group. We say that
is
well-based if it contains no infinite ascending chain
(equivalently, this means that
is well-ordered
for the opposite ordering). We denote by
the class of functions
whose support
is a well-based. The elements of are
called monomials and the elements in
are called
terms. We also define
and elements are called terms in
.
We see elements of
as
formal well-based series
where
for all
.
If
, then
is called the dominant monomial of
. For
,
we define
and
. For
, we sometimes
write
if
. We say that a series
is a
truncation of
and we write
if
.
The relation
is a well-founded partial order on
with minimum
.
By [27], the class is field for the
pointwise sum
and the Cauchy product
where each sum is finite. The class
is actually an ordered field, whose positive cone
is defined by
The ordered group is naturally embedded into
.
The relations and
on
extend to
by
We also write whenever
and
. If
are non-zero, then
(resp.
,
resp.
) if and
only if
(resp.
, resp.
).
Series in ,
and
are respectively called purely
large, infinitesimal, and positive infinite.
If is a family in
,
then we say that
is well-based
if
is well-based, and
is finite for all
.
Then we may define the sum of
as the series
If is another field of well-based series and
is
-linear,
then we say that
is strongly linear if
for every well-based family
in
, the family
in
is well-based, with
The field of logarithmic
hyperseries plays an important role in the theory of
hyperseries. Let us briefly recall its definition and its most prominent
properties from [17].
Let be an ordinal. For each
, we introduce the formal hyperlogarithm
and define
to be
the group of formal power products
with
. This group comes with a monomial
ordering
that is defined by
By what precedes, is an ordered field
of well-based series. If
are ordinals with
, then we define
to be the subgroup of
of monomials
with
whenever
. As in [17], we define
We have natural inclusions ,
hence natural inclusions
.
The field is equipped with a derivation
which satisfies the Leibniz rule and which is
strongly linear: for each
,
we first define the logarithmic derivative of
by
. The derivative of a
logarithmic hypermonomial
is next defined by
Finally, this definition extends to by strong
linearity. Note that
for all
. For
and
, we will sometimes write
.
Assume that for a certain ordinal
. Then the field
is
also equipped with a composition
that satisfies:
For , the map
is a strongly linear embedding [17, Lemma
6.6].
For and
,
we have
and
[17, Proposition 7.14].
For and successor ordinals
, we have
[17,
Lemma 5.6].
The same properties hold for the composition , when
is replaced by
. For
,
the map
is injective, with range
[17, Lemma 5.11]. For
, we define
to be
the unique series in
with
.
Following [26], we define as the
class of sequences
of “signs” indexed by arbitrary
ordinals
. We will write
for the domain of such a sequence and
for its value at
. Given sign
sequences
and
,
we define
Conway showed how to define an ordering, an addition, and a
multiplication on that give
the structure of a real closed field [14]. See [5,
Section 2] for more details about the interaction between
and the ordered field structure of
. By [14, Theorem 21], there is a
natural isomorphism between
and the ordered
field of well-based series
,
where
is a certain subgroup of
. We will identify those two fields and thus
regard
as a field of well-based series with
monomials in
.
The partial order contains an isomorphic copy of
obtained by identifying each ordinal
with the constant sequence
of
length
. We will write
to specify that
is either an
ordinal or the class of ordinals. The ordinal
, seen as a surreal number, is the simplest element,
or
-minimum, of the class
.
For , we write
and
for the
non-commutative ordinal sum and product of
and
, as defined by Cantor. The
surreal sum and product
and
coincide with the commutative Hessenberg sum and product of ordinals. In
general, we therefore have
and
.
For , we write
for the ordinal exponentiation of base
at
.
Gonshor also defined an exponential function on
with range
. One should not
confuse
with
,
which yields a different number, in general. We define
Recall that every ordinal has a unique Cantor
normal form
where ,
and
with
.
The ordinals
are called the exponents of
and the integers
its coefficients. We write
(resp.
) if each
exponent
of the Cantor normal form of
satisfies
(resp.
).
If are ordinals, then we write
if
, we write
if there exists an
with
, and we write
if both
and
hold. The relation
is a
quasi-order on
. For
with
and
, we have
.
In particular, we have
for all
.
If is a successor, then we define
to be the unique ordinal with
. We also define
if
is a limit. Similarly, if
, then we write
.
We already noted that Gonshor constructed an exponential and a logarithm
on and
,
respectively. We defined hyperexponential and hyperlogarithmic functions
of all strengths on
in [6]. In
fact, we showed [6, Theorem 1.1] how to construct a
composition law
with the following
properties:
Note that the composition law on also satisfies
to
(but not
), with each
occurrence of
being replaced by
.
For , we write
for the function
,
called the hyperlogarithm of strength
. By
and
, this is a strictly increasing bijection. We
sometimes write
for
. We write
for the
functional inverse of
,
called the hyperexponential of strength
.
For with
,
the relation
in
,
combined with
, yields
![]() |
(3.1) |
For , the relation
in
, combined
with
, yields
![]() |
(3.2) |
and we call this relation the functional equation
for .
Let and write
for the
coefficient in
in the Hahn series representation
of
. There is a unique
infinitesimal number
with
. We write
for the natural
logarithm on
. The function
defined by
![]() |
(3.3) |
is called the logarithm on . This is a strictly increasing morphism
which extends
.
It also coincides with the logarithm on
that was
defined by Gonshor.
Given , we write
for the class of numbers
with
for all
.
Those numbers are said to be
-atomic and they play an important role in this paper. Note that
and
for all , in view of (3.1). There is a unique
-atomic
number [6, Proposition 6.20], which is the simplest
positive infinite number
.
Each hyperlogarithmic function with
is essentially determined by its restriction to
, through a generalization of (3.3). More precisely, for
,
there exist
and
with
. Moreover, the family
is well-based, and the hyperlogarithm
is given by
![]() |
(3.4) |
is
-truncated
if
, i.e. if
is positive and purely large. For
, we say that
is
-truncated if
If is defined, then
is
-truncated if and only
if
, for all
.
Given with
,
we write
for the class of
-truncated numbers. Note that
. We will sometimes write
when
. For
, there is a unique
-maximal truncation
of
which is
-truncated. By [7, Proposition 7.17],
the classes
![]() |
(3.5) |
with form a partition of
into convex subclasses. Moreover, the series
is both the unique
-truncated
element and the
-minimum of
the convex class containing
.
We have
by [6, Proposition 7.6]. This allows us to define a map
by
.
In other words,
for all (see also [7, Corollary
7.23]).
The formulas (3.3) and (3.4) admit
hyperexponential analogues. For all ,
there is a
with
.
For any such
, there is a
family
with
such that
is well-based and
![]() |
(3.6) |
See [7, Section 7.1] for more details on . The number
is a
monomial with
, so
![]() |
(3.7) |
In [5], we introduced the notion of surreal
substructure. A surreal substructure is a subclass of
such that
and
are isomorphic. The isomorphism
is unique and denoted by
.
For the study of
as a hyperserial field, many
important subclasses of
turn out to be surreal
substructures. In particular, given
,
it is known that the following classes are surreal substructures:
The classes ,
and
of positive, positive
infinite and infinitesimal numbers.
The classes and
of
monomials and infinite monomials.
The classes and
of
purely infinite and positive purely infinite numbers.
The class of
-atomic
numbers.
The class of
-truncated
numbers.
We will prove in Section 6 that certain classes of nested numbers also form surreal substructures.
Given a subclass of
and
, we define
If is a subclass of
and
are subsets of
with
, then the class
is called a cut in .
If
contains a unique simplest element, then we
denote this element by
and say that
is a cut representation (of
) in
.
These notations naturally extend to the case when
and
are subclasses of
with
.
A surreal substructure may be characterized as a
subclass of
such that for all cut
representations
in
,
the cut
has a unique simplest element [5,
Proposition 4.7].
Let be a surreal substructure. Note that we have
for all
.
Let
and let
be a cut
representation of
in
. Then
is cofinal with
respect to
in the sense that
has no strict upper bound in
and
has no strict lower bound in
[5, Proposition 4.11(b)].
Let be a subclass, let
be a surreal substructure and
be a function. Let
be functions defined for cut representations in
such that
are subsets of
whenever
is a cut
representation in
. We say
that
is a cut equation for
if for all
,
we have
Elements in (resp.
)
are called left (resp. right)
options of this cut equation at
. We say that the cut equation is
uniform if
for all cut representations in
. For instance, given
, consider the translation
on
. By [26,
Theorem 3.2], we have the following uniform cut equation for
on
:
![]() |
(4.1) |
Let with
and set
. We have the following uniform cut
equations for
on
and
on
[6,
Section 8.1]:
where
A function group on a
surreal substructure
is a set-sized group of
strictly increasing bijections
under functional
composition. We see elements
of
as actions on
and sometimes write
and
for
rather than
and
.
We also write
for the functional inverse of
.
Given such a function group ,
the collection of classes
with forms a partition of
into convex subclasses. For subclasses
,
we write
. An element
is said to be
-simple if it is the simplest element inside
. We write
for
the class of
-simple
elements. Given
, we also
define
to be the unique
-simple element of
. The function
is a
non-decreasing projection of
onto
. The main purpose of function groups is to
define surreal substructures:
is a surreal substructure.
We have the uniform cut equation
![]() |
(4.6) |
Note that for , we have
if and only if
.
We have the following criterion to identify the
-simple elements inside
.
of
is
-simple if and only if there is a cut
representation
of
in
with
.
Equivalently, the number
is
-simple if and only if
.
Given be sets of strictly increasing bijections
, we define
If , then we say that
is pointwise cofinal with respect to
. For
,
we also write
or
instead
of
and
.
Given a function group on
, we define a partial order
on
by
.
We will frequently rely on the elementary fact that this ordering is
compatible with the group structure in the sense that
Given a set of strictly increasing bijections
, we define
to be the smallest function group on
that is
generated by
,
i.e.
.
The examples of surreal substructures from the beginning of this section
can all be obtained as classes of
-simplest elements for suitable function groups
that act on
,
, or
, as we will describe now. Given
and
, we first define
For , we then have the
following function groups
Now the action of on
yields the surreal substructure
as class of
-simplest elements. All
examples from the beginning of this section can be obtained in a similar
way:
The action of on
(resp.
) yields
(resp.
).
The action of on
(resp.
) yields
(resp.
).
The action of on
yields
.
The action of on
yields
.
The action of on
yields
.
We have
Let and
.
We will need a few inequalities from [6]. The first one is
immediate by definition and the fact that
.
The others are [6, Lemma 6.9, Lemma 6.11, and Proposition
6.17], in that order:
From (4.10), we also deduce that
![]() |
(4.11) |
In this section, we prove Theorem 1.1, i.e. that each number is well-nested. In Section 5.1 we start with the definition and study of hyperserial expansions. We pursue with the study of paths and well-nestedness in Section 5.2.
The general idea behind our proof of Theorem 1.1 is as
follows. Assume for contradiction that there exists a number that is not well-nested and choose a simplest (i.e.
-minimal) such number. By
definition,
contains a so-called “bad
path”. For the ill-nested number
from (1.6), that would be the sequence
From this sequence, we next construct a “simpler” number like
that still contains a bad path
thereby contradicting the minimality assumption on . In order to make this idea work, we first
need a series of “deconstruction lemmas” that allow us to
affirm that
is indeed simpler than
; these lemmas will be listed in Section 5.3. We will also need a generalization
of the relation
that was used by Berarducci and
Mantova to prove the well-nestedness of
as a
field of transseries; this will be the subject of Section 5.4.
We prove Theorem 1.1 in Section 5.5.
Unfortunately, the relation
does not have all
the nice properties of
. For
this reason, Sections 5.4 and 5.5 are quite
technical.
Recall that any number can be written as a well-based series. In order
to represent numbers as hyperseries, it therefore suffices to devise a
means to represent the infinitely large monomials
in
. We do this by taking a
hyperlogarithm
of the monomial and then
recursively applying the same procedure for the monomials in this new
series. This procedure stops when we encounter a monomial in
.
Technically speaking, instead of directly applying a hyperlogarithm to the monomial, it turns out to be necessary to
first decompose
as a product
and write
as a hyperexponential (or more
generally as the hyperlogarithm of a hyperexponential). This naturally
leads to the introduction of hyperserial expansions of
monomials
, as we will detail
now.
. Assume
that there are
,
,
,
and
such that
![]() |
(5.1) |
with . Then we say that
;
;
.
We say that and
, so
that
and
![]() |
(5.2) |
Formally speaking, hyperserial expansions can be represented by tuples
. By convention, we also
consider
to be a hyperserial expansion of the monomial ; this expansion is represented by the tuple
.
Example
and show how it can be expressed as a hyperseries. Note that
is tail-atomic since is log-atomic. Now
is a hyperserial expansion of type II and we have
. Hence
is a hyperserial expansion.
Let , so
. We may further expand each monomial in
. We clearly have
. We claim that
.
Indeed, if we could write
for some
and
, then
and
would both be monomials,
which cannot be. Note that
,
so
is a hyperserial expansion of type I. We also
have
where
is tail
expanded. Thus
is a hyperserial expansion. Note
finally that
is a hyperserial expansion. We thus
have the following “recursive” expansion of
:
![]() |
(5.3) |
Proof. We first prove the result for , by induction with respect to the
simplicity relation
. The
-minimal element of
is
, which
satisfies (5.2) for
and
. Consider
such that the result holds on
.
By [6, Proposition 6.20], the monomial
is not
-atomic. So there is a
maximal
with
,
and we have
by our hypothesis.
If there is no ordinal such that
, then we have
.
So setting
,
and
, we are done. Otherwise,
let
be such that
.
We cannot have
by definition of
. So there is a unique ordinal
and a unique natural number
such that
and
. Note that
. We must have
: otherwise,
where
and
are monomials. We deduce
that
and
.
Note that
,
, and
,
so
. We deduce that
. The induction hypothesis yields a
hyperserial expansion
. Since
is log-atomic, we must have
and
. If
, then
,
since
. Thus
is a hyperexponential expansion of type II. If
, then likewise
and thus
is a hyperexponential expansion of type I. This
completes the inductive proof.
Now let and set
.
If
is tail-atomic, then there are
,
and
with
. Applying the previous
arguments to
, we obtain
elements
with
and
, or an ordinal
with
. Then
or
is a hyperserial expansion. If
is not tail-atomic, then we have
is a hyperserial expansion of type I.
.
Let
and define
if
is a successor ordinal and
if
is a limit ordinal. Let
Proof. We first prove ). Assume that
is
-atomic. Assume for contradiction
that
and let
denote the
least non-zero term in the Cantor normal form of
. Since
,
we have
so
is a
monomial. But
where
is a
monomial: a contradiction. So
.
If
then we are done. Otherwise
, so we must have
,
whence
. Conversely, assume
that
or
,
and that
. If
, then then for all
, we have
where
, so
is a monomial,
whence
. If
, then for all
,
we have
, whence
. This proves
).
Now assume that . So
is
-atomic
by
). If
then we conclude that
. If
, then let
denote the least non-zero term in its Cantor normal form. We have
and
, so
.
Proof. Since ,
we must have
. By Lemma 5.4, we have a hyperserial expansion
. Since
is log-atomic, we
have
, whence
and
. So
. We have
so by Lemma 5.5(a), we have
. It follows that
is a
hyperserial expansion. But then
and Lemma 5.5(a) imply that
. The condition that
now
gives
, whence
is a successor and
for a certain
, as claimed.
has a unique hyperserial expansion
(that we will call
Proof. Consider a monomial
with
where ,
,
,
,
, and
.
Assume for contradiction that we can write
as a
hyperserial expansion of type I with
.
Note in particular that
, so
is log-atomic. We have
If , then
,
,
, and
is not tail-atomic. But
,
where
, so
is tail-atomic: a contradiction. Hence
.
Note that
and
are both
the least term of
. It
follows that
,
, and
![]() |
(5.4) |
Since , we have
Now , so
and thus
. In particular
. Taking hyperexponentials on
both sides of (5.4), we may assume without loss of
generality that
or that the least exponents
and
in the Cantor normal
forms of
resp.
differ. If
, then we
decompose
where
and
. Since
, applying Lemma 5.5(a)
twice (for
and
)
gives
and
,
whence
. But then
, where
by
Lemma 5.5(a). So
: a contradiction. Assume now that
. Lemma 5.5(a)
yields both
and
,
which contradicts (5.4).
Taking and
,
this proves that no two hyperserial expansions of distinct types I and
II can be equal. Taking
with
, this proves that no two hyperserial
expansions
of type I with
can be equal.
The two remaining cases are hyperserial expansions of type II and
hyperserial expansions and
of type I with
. Consider a
monomial
with the hyperserial expansions
of type II. As above we have
,
, and
. We deduce that
, so the expansions coincide.
Finally, consider a monomial with two
hyperserial expansions of type I
![]() |
(5.5) |
If , then we have
and
and
, whence
,
so we are done.
Assume now that . Taking
logarithms in (5.5), we see that
,
, and
![]() |
(5.6) |
We may assume without loss of generality that . Assume for contradiction that
. Taking hyperexponentials on both sides of (5.6), we may assume without loss of generality that
or that the least exponents
and
in the Cantor normal forms of
resp.
differ. On the one hand,
Lemma 5.5(a) yields
. Note in particular that
, since
.
On the other hand, if
, then
Lemma 5.5(a) yields
; if
,
then
. Thus (5.6)
is absurd: a contradiction. We conclude that
. Finally
yields
, so the expansions are
identical.
Proof. Assume for contradiction that . In particular
. Since
,
there is
with
,
so
: a contradiction.
Let be an ordinal with
and note that
for all
. Consider a sequence
We say that is a path if
there exist sequences
,
,
,
, and
with
and
;
or
for all
;
for all
;
For , the hyperserial
expansion of
is
We call the length of
and we write
. We say that
is infinite if
and
finite otherwise. We set
.
For
, we define
![]() |
By Lemma 5.8, those cases are mutually exclusive so is well-defined. For
,
we say that
is a path in
if
.
For , we let
denote the path of length
in
with
Example of Example 5.3. We have a representation (5.3) of
as a hyperseries
which by Lemma 5.7 is unique. There are nine paths in , namely
one path of length
;
three paths ,
, and
of length
;
three paths ,
and
of length
;
two paths and
of
length
.
Note that the paths which cannot be extended into strictly longer paths
are those whose last value is a real number or .
Infinite paths occur in so-called nested numbers that will be studied in more detail in Section 6.
and let
be a path in a. We say that an index
is bad for
if one of the following conditions is satisfied
The index is
good for
if it is not bad for
.
If is infinite, then we say that it is
good if
is good for all but a finite number of indices. In the opposite case,
we say that
is a bad
path. An element
is said to be
well-nested every path in
is good.
Remark with with
(whence
) for all
,
corresponds to a path for these former definitions. The validity of the
axiom T4 for
means that those
paths are good. With Theorem 1.1, we will extend this
result to all paths.
Proof. Let and let
be a path in
.
If there is an ordinal
with
, then the hyperserial expansion of
is
, so
if
and
otherwise. If there is an ordinal
with
, then the hyperserial expansion of
is
and
.
Assume now that . If
is not tail-atomic, then hyperserial expansion of
is
.
If
is tail-atomic, then the hyperserial
expansion of
is
for a
certain log-atomic
. In both
cases,
is a path in some monomial in
, whence
and
, by the previous
argument.
be paths. We say that
is a subpath of
, or equivalently that
extends
, if there exists a
with
. For
, we say that
is a
subpath in
if there
is a path
in
such that
is a subpath of
.
We say that
shares a subpath
with
if there is a subpath of
which is a subpath in
.
Let be a finite path and let
be a path with
. Then we
define
to be the path
of length
.
Proof. By Lemma 5.12, we have . If
has a
hyperserial expansion of the form
,
then
must be a path in
. So
is non-zero and thus
. It follows that
is a path in
.
Otherwise, let
be the hyperserial expansion of
. If
is a path in
, then it is a
path in
as above. Otherwise, it is a path in
. Assume that
. If
,
then we have
and
so
is a path in
.
If
, then
where
is a hyperserial expansion, so
is a path in
.
Assume now that
, so
,
,
and
. We must have
so there are
and
with
and
.
We have
where
is a
hyperserial expansion, so
is a path in
.
Proof. We prove this by induction on , for any number
. We consider
,
and a fixed path
in
with
.
Assume that . We have
and
.
Assume that
for certain
,
, and
. Let
be the hyperserial expansion of
.
If
, then
and the hyperserial expansion of
is
. Therefore
is a
subpath in
. If
, then the hyperserial expansion of
is
. Therefore
is a subpath in
.
Finally, if
is not tail-atomic, then
is a subpath in
,
where
is the sign of
.
Now assume that ,
, and that the result holds
strictly below
. We have
where
is a subpath in
by the previous argument. We have
for a certain
, so
is a path in
.
The induction hypothesis on
implies that
is a subpath in
.
Assume now that and that the result holds
strictly below
. Write
. By (3.7), there
exist
,
, and
with
and
Assume for contradiction that there is a with
. We must have
, so there are a number
and an ordinal
with
. We have
.
By Lemma 5.12, this contradicts the fact that
. So by Lemma 5.4, there exist
and
with
,
,
, and
. Since
,
we must have
so there are a number
and an ordinal
with
(note that
whenever
). Thus
is a monomial
with hyperserial expansion
.
There is no path in
of length
, so
must be a path in
. We deduce that
is a path in
.
Consequently,
is a path in
with
. Applying
times Lemma 5.14, we deduce that
is a subpath in
,
hence in
. Consider a path
in
with
for a certain
. Applying the
induction hypothesis for
and
in the roles of
and
, the path
is a subpath in
. Therefore
is a subpath in
. We deduce
as in the case
that
is a
subpath in
.
Proof. Let be a
hyperserial expansion. The condition
implies
, whence
is also a hyperserial expansion. In particular
is a subpath in
.
,
with
,
and
. If
is an infinite path, then
shares a subpath
with
if and only if it shares a subpath with
.
Proof. Write in Cantor
normal form, with
and
and let
for all .
Assume that shares a subpath with
. In other words, there is a path
in
which has a common subpath with
. The path
must be infinite, so by Lemma 5.15, it shares a subpath
with
. Let us prove by
induction on
that
shares
a subpath with
. Assuming
that this holds for
, we note
that
is
-atomic,
hence
-atomic. So
shares a subpath with
by Lemma 5.14 and the induction hypothesis. We conclude by induction
that
shares a subpath with
.
Suppose conversely that shares a subpath with
. By induction on
, it follows from Lemma 5.15
that
shares a subpath with
. Applying Lemma 5.14 to
, we conclude that
shares a subpath with
.
In this subsection, we list several results on the interaction between
the simplicity relation and various operations
in
.
Proof. The condition
yields
. We have
by Lemma 5.23. The identity
implies that
, whence
by Lemma 5.21. Consequently,
, by Lemma 5.22. Since
, we may apply Lemma 5.22
to
and
to obtain
. We conclude using the
transitivity of
.
Proof. By (4.5), we have
Since , we have
and
, whence
Furthermore, we have , so
. We conclude that
.
In [10, Section 8], the authors prove the well-nestedness
axiom for
by relying on
a well-founded partial order
that is
defined by induction. This relation has the additional property that
In this subsection, we define a similar relation
on
that will be instrumental in deriving results
on the structure of
.
However, this relation does not satisfy
for all
.
Given , we define
where is a sequence of relations that are
defined by induction on
, as
follows. For
, we set
, if
or if
there exist decompositions
with and
.
Assuming that
has been defined, we set
if we are in one of the two following configurations:
where ,
,
,
,
,
,
and . If
, then we also require that
.
where ,
,
,
,
, and
.
Warning in the first configuration, we see that
extends
.
However, the relation
is neither transitive nor
anti-symmetric. Furthermore, as we already noted above, we do
not have
.
Proof. Let and
. Assume for contradiction that
and
.
Assume first that
, so
. Then
. Let
be such that
. Since
, we deduce that
,
whence
. Modulo replacing
by
,
it follow that we may assume without loss of generality that
for some
and some monomial
.
On the one hand, is not
-truncated, so there are
and
with
and
. We may choose
for
certain
and
,
so
. On the other hand,
is
-truncated,
so we have
We deduce that . If
is a successor, then choosing
, we obtain
,
so
: a contradiction.
Otherwise,
by [7, (2.4)], where
. Thus
, whence
:
a contradiction.
We now treat the general case. By a similar argument as above, we may
assume without loss of generality that .
Assume that
. Since
is not
-truncated,
there exists a
with
, whence
.
But
is
-truncated,
so
. In particular
, so our hypothesis
implies that
:
a contradiction.
Assume now that . As in the
first part of the proof, there are
and
with
and
. Recall that
for
sufficiently large
. Take
and
such that
Then . If
is a successor, then choosing
yields
, which contradicts the fact that
and
are infinitesimal.
So
is a limit. Writing
, we have
.
As in the first part of the proof, we obtain
, so
. In
view of (5.11), we also obtain
, so
: a
contradiction.
Proof. Assume that .
Let
and let
be its
functional inverse in
. We
have
by (4.10, 4.11),
whence
. Furthermore,
, so
![]() |
(5.12) |
We want to prove that . By
(5.12), it is enough to prove that there is a
such that the inequality
holds on
.
Assume that . Setting
, we have
, whence
,
and
.
Assume that . We have
so
by (4.8).
Thus
. Consequently,
, as claimed.
If are numbers, then we write
for the interval
.
Proof. We prove this by induction on with
. Let
be an infinite path in
.
Assume that
. If
, then we have
so
is a path in
.
Otherwise, there are
,
and
with
and
. Then
for certain
,
and
with
. We must have
.
If
is a path in
,
then it is a path in
.
Otherwise, it is a path in
,
so
is a subpath in
,
hence in
.
We now assume that where
and that the result holds for all
and
with
and
. Assume first that
is in Configuration I, and write
Then we can write like in the case when
. If
is a
path in
, then it is a path
in
. So we may assume that
is a path in
.
Note that we have
. Setting
, we observe that
, whence
is
the hyperserial expansion of
.
If
is a path in
,
then it is a path in
.
Suppose that is not a path in
. Assume first that
, so
,
, and
is a path in
. Then Lemma 5.14 implies that
is a subpath in
, so
is a subpath in
. Otherwise,
consider the hyperserial expansion
,
of
.
Since
is not a path in
, it must be a path in
.
The number
is
-atomic,
so we must have
and
. There are
and
such that
.
Therefore
. It follows by
Corollary 5.17 that
shares a
subpath with
, whence so does
.
Let . Recall that
, so
.
Now (4.8) implies that
,
so
. The function
is non-decreasing, so
.
But
, so the induction
hypothesis yields that
, and
thus
, shares a subpath with
. We deduce with Lemma 5.15 that
shares a subpath with
, hence with
.
Assume now that is in Configuration
II, and write
Note that we also have . We
may again assume that
is a path in
. Write
,
where
,
, and
.
Then
where
.
We deduce by induction that
shares a subpath
with
. By Lemma 5.15,
it follows that
shares a subpath with
, hence with
. This concludes the proof.
and
with
. Let
be of the form
with ,
,
,
,
,
and
. Consider an infinite path
in
with
.
Proof. i. If , then we have
,
so
. Let
with
. Since
and
are monomials, we have
, whence
.
Our assumption that
also implies
. Hence
.
Now
shares a subpath with
, by Lemma 5.15. Since
, Proposition 5.29 next implies
that
shares a subpath with
. Using Lemma 5.14, we conclude
that
shares a subpath with
, and hence with
.
ii. Let with
. It is enough to prove that
shares a subpath with
. Since
,
, and
are monomials, we have
. Let
, so that
.
In particular, we have
.
Moreover
, so using Lemma 5.15 and Proposition 5.29, we deduce in the same
way as above that
shares a subpath with
. If
,
then
is the hyperserial expansion of
, so
shares
a subpath with
. If
, then the hyperserial expansion of
must be of the form
, since otherwise
would have
at least two elements in its support. We deduce that
shares a subpath with
and that the hyperserial
expansion of
is
.
Therefore
shares a subpath with
.
iii. We assume that is not
-truncated whereas
and
. If
, then we must have
, which means that
or that
and
.
But then
: a contradiction.
Assume that . By Lemma 5.27, we may assume without loss of generality that
. The assumption on
and the fact that
imply that
is non-zero. Write
So and
.
Note that
must be infinitesimal since
is not
-truncated.
Thus
is also infinitesimal. By Lemma 5.27,
we deduce that
. We have
, so
, since
and
are both
-truncated. Since
is not
-truncated,
there is an ordinal
with
. If
,
then
, because
is
-truncated.
Thus
. If
, then
,
because
and
are
-truncated. Now
, since
.
We again deduce that
.
In both cases, we have where
, so
shares a subpath
with
, by Proposition 5.29. It follows by Corollary 5.17 that
shares a subpath with
.
We now prove that every number is well-nested. Throughout this
subsection, will be an infinite path inside a
number
. At the beginning of
Section 5.2 we have shown how to attach sequences
,
,
etc. to this path. In order to alleviate notations, we will
abbreviate
,
,
,
,
,
, and
for all
.
We start with a technical lemma that will be used to show that the
existence of a bad path in
implies the existence of a bad path in a strictly simpler number than
.
, let
be an infinite path in
and let
such that every index
is good for
. For
, let
,
, and
, so that
and
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
(k<i) |
![]() |
![]() |
![]() |
Let and let
be a
number with
and
![]() |
(5.13) |
for a certain with
,
and
whenever
. For
, we define
![]() |
(5.14) |
Assume that shares a subpath with
. If
shares no subpath with any of the numbers
, then we have
,
and
shares a subpath with
.
Proof. Using backward induction on , let us prove for
that
and that (5.19) and (5.21)
also hold for
.
We first treat the case when .
Note that
since it contains a subpath, so
or
. From
our assumption that
and the fact that
if
, we deduce
that
. Hence
and (5.15)
. Note that (5.19)
and (5.20)
follow immediately from the other assumptions
on
. If
then
. If
, then
,
since
and
.
Hence
by Lemma 5.21 and
by Lemmas 5.19 and 5.22.
Finally,
by Lemma 5.20, so (5.21)
holds in general.
Recall that
is a subpath in
, but that it shares no subpath with
or
. In view of
(5.20)
, we deduce (5.16)
from Lemma 5.30(i) and (5.17)
from Lemma 5.30(ii). Combining (5.16)
, (5.17)
and (5.20)
with the
relation
, we finally obtain
(5.18)
.
Let and assume that (5.15–5.21)
hold for all
. We shall prove (5.15–5.21)
if
, as well as (5.19)
and (5.21)
.
Recall that
Recall that . If
or
,
then
and (5.16–5.17)
imply (5.15)
. Assume now that
.
It follows since
that
, so
and
. Since
is a hyperserial expansion, we must have
, so
.
The result now follows from (5.15)
and Lemma 5.28.
We know by (5.19)
that
shares a subpath with
. Since
,
we deduce with Corollary 5.17 that
also shares a subpath with
,
hence with
. In view of
(5.16)
and Lemma 5.16, we see that
shares a
subpath with
. Hence (5.17)
gives that
shares
a subpath with
.
By (5.18), we have
. Now
shares a subpath with
by (5.19)
, but it shares no subpath with
. Lemma 5.30(i) therefore yields the desired result
.
As above, shares a subpath with
, but no subpath with
. We also have
and
, so
(5.17)
follows from
Lemma 5.30(ii).
The path shares a subpath with
, but no subpath with
. By what precedes, we also
have
and
.
Note finally that
.
Hence
, by applying
Lemma 5.30(iii) with
,
,
,
, and
in the
roles of
,
,
,
, and
.
It suffices to prove that ,
since
Assume that and recall that
By Lemma 5.25, it suffices to prove that and that
for all
. The first relation holds by
(5.21)
. By (5.15)
, we have
. Therefore
by Lemma 5.25. This yields the result.
Assume now that . For
, let
We will prove, by a second descending induction on , that the monomials
and
satisfy the premises of Lemma 5.24,
i.e.
,
, and
. It will then follow by Lemma 5.24
that
, thus concluding
the proof.
If , then
, because
.
In particular
.
Moreover,
follows from our assumption that
, the fact that
, and Lemmas 5.22
and 5.21. If
,
then we have
because
. Otherwise, we have
.
Now assume that , that
the result holds for
,
and that
. Again
implies that
.
The relation
and Lemmas 5.18,
5.19, and 5.20 imply that
. If
,
then
by (5.16)
. Otherwise, we have
, because
.
Since
, the number
is not tail-atomic, so we must have
. This entails that
and
. By
the induction hypothesis at
,
we have
. We deduce
that
, so
It follows by induction that (5.21) is valid.
This concludes our inductive proof. The lemma follows from (5.21) and (5.19)
.
We are now in a position to prove our first main theorem.
Proof of Theorem 1.1. Assume for
contradiction that the theorem is false. Let be
a
-minimal ill-nested number
and let
be a bad path in
. Let
be the smallest bad
index in
. As in Lemma 5.31, we define
,
, and
for all
. We may assume that
, otherwise the number
is ill-nested and satisfies
: a contradiction.
Assume for contradiction that there is a such
that
or
is ill-nested.
Set
if
is ill-nested and
otherwise. If
,
then
cannot share a subpath with
, so
by Lemma 5.30,
and
is ill-nested. In general, it follows that
is ill-nested. Let
be a
bad path in
and set
. Then we may apply Lemma 5.31 to
,
,
and
in the roles of
,
, and
. Since
, this yields an ill-nested number
: a contradiction.
Therefore the numbers are well-nested. Since
is bad for
,
one of the four cases listed in Definition 5.10 must occur.
We set
By construction, we have .
Furthermore
shares a subpath with
, so there exists a bad path
in
. We have
by Lemma 5.27. If Definition 5.10(4)
occurs, then we must have
so
is written as in (5.13) with
in the
role of
and
.
Otherwise,
is as in (5.13) for
. Setting
, it follows that we may apply Lemma 5.31
to
and
in the roles of
and
.
We conclude that there exists an ill-nested number
: a contradiction.
In the previous section, we have examined the nature of infinite paths in surreal numbers and shown that they are ultimately “well-behaved”. In this section, we work in the opposite direction and show how to construct surreal numbers that contain infinite paths of a specified kind. We follow the same method as in [5, Section 8].
Let us briefly outline the main ideas. Our aim is to construct “nested numbers” that correspond to nested expressions like
Nested expressions of this kind will be presented through so-called
coding sequences .
Once we have fixed such a coding sequence
,
numbers
of the form (6.1) need to
satisfy a sequence of natural inequalities: for any
with
, we require that
Numbers that satisfy these constraints are said to be admissible. Under suitable conditions, the class Ad of admissible numbers forms a convex surreal substructure. This will be detailed in Sections 6.1 and 6.2, where we will also introduce suitable coordinates
for working with numbers in .
The notation (6.1) also suggests that each of the numbers
,
,
should be a monomial. An
admissible number
is said to be nested
if this is indeed the case. The main result of this section is Theorem
1.2, i.e. that the class
of nested numbers forms a surreal substructure. In other words, the
notation (6.1) is ambiguous, but can be disambiguated using
a single surreal parameter.
Taking for all
,
we obtain a reformulation of the notion of coding sequences in [5,
Section 8.1]. If
is a coding sequence and
, then we write
which is also a coding sequence.
be an infinite path in a number
without any bad index for
. Let
and
for all
. Then
is a coding sequence.
Proof. Let .
We have
because
is a
good index for
. We have
and
by the definition of
hyperserial expansions. If
and
, then we have
because
by the definition of paths. Lemma 5.27
also yields
. This proves the
conditions
) and
) for coding sequences. Assume that
. Then by the definition of
hyperserial expansions, we have
and
is not tail-atomic. Assume that
. Then
so
. We have
where
and
is not tail-atomic. This
implies that
is not log-atomic, so
. Thus
)
is valid.
Assume that . Recall that
, so
. Since
,
we have
, whence
. This proves
).
Assume now for contradiction that there is an
with
for all
.
By
), we have
for all
, and
the sequence
is non-increasing, hence eventually
constant. Let
with
for
all
. For
, we have
so
. Therefore
is
-atomic: a contradiction.
We deduce that
) holds as
well.
We next fix some notations. For all with
, we define partial functions
,
and
on
by
The domains of these functions are assumed to be largest for which these expressions make sense. We also write
We note that on their respective domains, the functions ,
,
and
are strictly increasing if
,
,
and
, respectively, and
strictly decreasing in the contrary cases. We will write
and
for the partial inverses of
and
.
We will also use the abbreviations
For all , we set
Note that
The following lemma generalizes [5, Lemma 8.1].
, then
is well defined for all
.
Proof. Let us prove the lemma by induction on
. The result clearly holds
for
. Assuming that
is well defined, let
be minimal
such that
or
.
Note that we have
, so
where
.
Applying
to the inequality
we obtain
Now if , then
whence
Both in the cases when and when
, it follows that
is
bounded from below by the hyperexponential
of a
number. Thus
is well defined and so is each
for
. If
, then we have
and
Hence
Both in the cases when and when
, it follows that
is
bounded from below by the hyperexponential
of a
number, so
is well defined and so is each
for
.
be a coding sequence
and let
. We say that
is
-admissible if
is well defined for all
and
We say that is
admissible if there exists a
-admissible number.
Note that we do not ask that be a hyperserial
expansion, nor even that
be a monomial. For the
rest of the section, we fix a coding sequence
. We write
for
the class of
-admissible
numbers. If
, then the
definition of
implicitly assumes that
is well defined for all
.
Note that if
is admissible, then so is
for
. We denote
by
the corresponding class of
-admissible numbers.
The main result of this subsection is the following generalization of [5, Proposition 8.2]:
Proof. Let and let
. We have
. If
,
then
is strictly increasing so we have
If , then
is strictly decreasing and likewise we obtain
.
We have . If
, then
is strictly
increasing so we have
Likewise, we have if
.
Assume that and
.
If
, then we have
. Hence
If , then we have
, whence
Symmetric arguments apply when and
.
We deduce by definition of that
.
As a consequence of this last proposition and [5,
Proposition 4.29(a)], the class is a surreal
substructure if and only if
is admissible.
Example where for all
, we have
We use the notations from Section 6.1. We claim that is admissible. Indeed for
, set
Given and
,
we have
and
.
We deduce that
, whence
is admissible.
Proof. For ,
we write
if
and
and
have the same sign. Let
us prove by induction on
that
is defined and that
. Since
this implies that
, that
, and that
if
, this will yield
.
The result follows from our hypothesis if .
Assume now that
and let us prove that
. Let
We have , so
is defined. Moreover
so
. Since
,
we deduce that
, whence in
particular
. This concludes
the proof.
Proof. For ,
and
, we have
so
. We
conclude with the previous lemma.
Proof. Let be minimal
with
or
.
We thus have
so
.
We have
and
where
. We deduce by induction using
Lemma 5.28 that
.
In this subsection, we assume that is
admissible. For
we say that a
-admissible number
is
-nested if we have
for all
. We
write
for the class of
-nested numbers. For
we
simply say that
is
-nested
and we write
.
Note that the inclusion always holds. In [5, Section 8.4], we gave examples of nested and admissible
non-nested sequences in the case of transseries, i.e. with
for all
. We
next give an example in the hyperserial case.
Example from Example 6.6
is nested. Indeed, let
and
. We have
for a certain
with
.
Let us check that the conditions of Definition 6.4 are
satisfied for
.
First let . We want to prove
that
. We have
for a certain
.
Now
, so
.
Secondly, let . We want to
prove that
. We have
for a certain
.
Then
by the previous paragraph. Now
so
.
Finally, we claim that . This
is immediate since the dominant term
of
is positive infinite, so
. Therefore
is nested.
A crucial feature of nested sequences is that they are sufficient to describe nested expansions. This is the content of Theorem 6.15 below.
. If
, or
and
is not tail-atomic, then the hyperserial
expansion of
is
If ,
is tail-atomic, and
is a hyperserial
expansion, then
and the hyperserial expansion
of
is
Proof. Recall that .
By Corollary 6.8, we have
,.
So we may assume without loss of generality that
.
We claim that . Assume for
contradiction that
and write
accordingly. Then Corollary 5.6 implies that
, in which case we define
, or
for some ordinal
and
for some
. Therefore
, so
.
This implies that
Recall that . Assume that
, so
. Since
is
-atomic, we also have
. Let
be minimal with
or
. We
have
and
.
In particular, the number
is log-atomic. If
, this contradicts the fact
that
. If
, then
implies
But then is not a monomial: a contradiction.
Assume now that
. So
and
. But
then
is not defined: a contradiction. We
conclude that
.
If , or if
and
is not tail-atomic, then our claim yields
the result. Assume now that
and that
is tail-atomic where
,
and
is a hyperserial expansion. Then the
hyperserial expansion of
is
.
We next show that . If
, then
, and we conclude with Lemma 6.7 that
. Assume for contradiction
that
. Since
is log-atomic, we must have
.
By the definition of coding sequences, this implies that
and
. So
, whence
,
, and
. In particular the number
is
-atomic,
hence tail-atomic. Since
,
the claim in the second paragraph of the proof, applied to
, gives
.
But then also
: a
contradiction.
We pursue with two auxiliary results that will be used order to construct a infinite path required in the proof of Theorem 6.15 below.
Proof. By Lemma 5.16, it is enough
to find such a path in .
Write
. Assume first that
, so
and
. If
is not tail-atomic, then the hyperserial expansion of
is
and
is the dominant
term of
for some
.
Then the path
with
and
satisfies
.
If
is tail-atomic, then there exist
,
and
such that the hyperserial expansion of
is
. Let
be a
term in
with
.
Then the path
with
and
satisfies
.
Assume now that . In view of
(3.6), we recall that there are an ordinal
and a number
with
If is a limit ordinal, then by Lemma 6.12,
we have a hyperserial expansion
.
Let
and set
and
, so that
is a path in
. By Lemma 5.15, there is a subpath in
,
hence also a path
in
, with
.
So
. If
is a successor ordinal, then we may choose
for a
certain
. By Lemma 6.12,
we have a hyperserial expansion
.
As in the previous case, there is a path
in
with
,
whence
.
Proof. This is immediate if . Assume that the result holds at
and pick a corresponding path
with
(resp.
).
Note that the dominant term
of
(resp.
) lies in
by Lemma 6.7. Moreover
is a term of
(resp.
). By the previous lemma, there is a path
in
with
or
, so
satisfies the conditions.
Proof. Assume for contradiction that this is not
the case. This means that the set of indices
such that we do not have
is infinite. We write
where
. Fix
and let
. Let
such
that
![]() |
(6.2) |
let and let
be any
finite path with
We claim that we can extend to a path
with
,
and such that
is a bad index
in
. Indeed, in view of
Definition 6.4 for
,
the relation (6.2) translates into the following three
possibilities:
There is an with
. We then have
.
By Lemma 6.7 and the convexity of
, we deduce that
lies in the class
, so
. By Corollary 6.14
for the admissible sequence starting with
and followed by
, there
is a finite path
in
with
and
.
Taking the logarithm and using Lemma 5.14, we obtain a
finite path
in
,
hence in
, with
and
. Write
where
and
. Then
, so the hyperserial expansion of
has one of the following forms
where is a hyperserial expansion and
is purely large. In both cases, the path
is a finite path
in
with
.
Since
is a term in
, we may consider the path
. Moreover, since
is a term in
, the index
is bad for
.
We have , but there is an
with
.
We then have
. By Lemma
6.7 and the convexity of
,
we deduce that
lies in
. So
lies in
. But then also
lies in
by Corollary 6.8.
By Corollary 6.14, there is a finite path
in
with
and
. Applying Lemma 5.15 to this path
in
, we obtain is a finite path
in
with
. Since
,
we have
. So Lemma 5.16 implies that there is a finite path
in
, hence in
, with
. We have
,
so
is a path. Write
for the dominant term of
.
The index
is a bad in
because
and
both lie
in
, and
.
We have and
,
but
. By the definition
of
-truncated numbers,
there is a
with
Using the convexity of ,
it follows that
. By
similar arguments as above (using Corollary 6.14 and
Lemmas 5.15 and 5.14), we deduce that
there is a finite path
in
with
. As in the previous
case
is a path and
is a bad index in
.
Consider a and the path
in
. So
is a finite path with
. Thus
there exists a path
which extends
with
, where
is a bad index in
.
Repeating this process iteratively for
,
we construct a path
that extends
and such that
and such that
is a bad index in
.
At the limit, this yields an infinite path
in
that extends each of the paths
. This path
has a
cofinal set of bad indices, which contradicts Theorem 1.1.
We conclude that there is a
such that
is nested.
Proof. Note that .
The result thus follows from Corollary 6.8 and the
assumption that
is nested.
is nested. Let
,
and
with
![]() |
(6.3) |
for a certain with
and
whenever
.
If
, then we have
Proof. The proof is similar to the proof of
Lemma 5.31. We have and we must
have
since
.
If follows from the deconstruction lemmas in Section 5.3
that
. This proves the result
in the case when
.
Now assume that . Setting
, let us prove by induction
on
that
For , the last relation
yields the desired result.
If , then we have
by assumption and we have shown above that
. We have
and
is a monomial, so (6.3) yields
. This deals with the case
. In addition, we have
because
and
.
Let us show that
![]() |
(6.4) |
If , then this follows from
the facts that
and
.
If
and
,
then
. If
, then
and
, so
.
Assume now that and that the induction
hypothesis holds for all smaller
.
We have
![]() |
(6.5) |
Since is nested, we immediately obtain
, whence
as
above. Since
and
is
nested, we have
. Using (6.5), (6.4), and the decomposition lemmas, we
observe that the relation
is equivalent to
![]() |
(6.6) |
We have , so
. Note that
So it is enough, in order to derive (6.6), to prove that
. Now
by Lemma 6.9, whence by Lemma 5.25.
For ,
and
, we have
by Lemma 6.16. We may thus consider the
strictly increasing bijection
We will prove Theorem 1.2 by proving that the function
group on
generates the
class
, i.e. that we have
. We first need the following
inequality:
Proof. It is enough to prove the result for
. Assume that
. Let
and set
, so that
Note that
If , then
and
is strictly increasing. So we only need to
prove that
, which reduces to
proving that
. Let
be the dominant term of
.
Our assumption that
is nested gives
, whence
.
We deduce that
. Lemma 5.27 implies that
is
-truncated.
and implies that
is a strictly positive term. We deduce that , whence
.
The other cases when
or when
are proved similarly, using symmetric arguments.
We are now in a position to prove the following refinement of Theorem 1.2.
Proof. By Proposition 4.1, the
class is a surreal substructure, so it is enough
to prove the equality. We first prove that
.
Assume for contradiction that there are an and a
, which we choose minimal,
such that
cannot be written as
where
is a hyperserial expansion. Set
,
and
.
Our goal is to prove that there is a number and
with
![]() |
(6.7) |
Assume that this is proved and set .
The first condition and Lemma 6.16 yield
and the relations
and
. The second and third condition, together with
Lemma 6.17, imply
.
The first condition also implies that
:
a contradiction. Proving the existence of
and
is therefore sufficient.
If or
and
, then
and
satisfy (6.7). Assume now that
and that
,
whence
. If
then
and
satisfy (6.7). Assume therefore that
.
This implies that there exist
and
with
By the definition of coding
sequences, there is a least index
with
or
, so
We have and
.
So by Corollary 5.6, we must have
for a certain
and
for a
certain
. Note that
. Recall that
and
, so
. The case
cannot occur
for otherwise
would not lie in . So
. Let
and
We have and
,
so
and
satisfy (6.7).
We deduce that
is a subclass of
.
Conversely, consider and set
. So there are
and
with
. Let
. By Lemma 6.18,
there exist
with
and
, whence
. Since
is strictly
monotonous, we get
. The
numbers
and
are
monomials, so
. Therefore
.
In view of Theorem 6.19, Lemma 6.18, and
Proposition 4.1, we have the following parametrization of
:
We conclude this section with a few remarkable identities for .
is nested, then for
and
, we have
.
Proof. By [5, Lemma 4.5] and since
the function is strictly monotonous, it is
enough to prove that
. By
induction, we may also restrict to the case when
. So assume that
.
Recall that
by Lemma 6.9. Since
, we deduce with Lemma 5.25 that
. It
follows using the decomposition lemmas that
.
is nested, then we have
.
Proof. We have by
definition of
. So we only
need to prove that
. Consider
. Since
is nested, the number
is
-admissible, so we need only justify that
. Since
is
-admissible, we have
. But
is
-nested, so
for a certain term
. We
deduce that
, whence
.
Assume for contradiction that and write
where
and
. Note that
:
otherwise
and
would be
zero for all
, thereby
contradicting Definition 6.1(e). By Corollary
5.6, we must have
for a certain
ordinal
and
for a
certain
. Consequently,
. If
,
then the condition
implies
, which leads to the contradiction that
. If
,
then
, whence
: a contradiction.
is nested with
, assume that
and write
. Consider the
coding sequence
with
for all
, with the only
exception that
If , or
and
, then
is nested and we have
where is the class of
-nested numbers.
Proof. Assume that ,
or
and
.
In particular, if
is
-admissible, then
,
so
. For
, it follows that
is
-admissible if and only if
is
-admissible.
Let
be the class of
-admissible numbers, for each
. We have
by the previous
remarks, and
is admissible. For
, we have
,
so
Moreover, , so
So is nested. We deduce that
, that is, we have a strictly increasing
bijection
. It is enough to
prove that for
with
, we have
.
Proceeding by induction on
,
we may assume without loss of generality that
. By [6, identity (6.3)], the function
has the following equation on
:
So it is enough to prove that .
Note that
and
where
. So
, whence
.
This concludes the proof.
Let be a number. We say that
is pre-nested if there exists an infinite path
in
without any bad index for
. In that case, Lemma 6.2 yields a
coding sequence
which is admissible due to the
fact that
with the notations from Section 6. By Theorem 6.15, we get a smallest
such that
is nested. If
, then we say that
is nested. In that case, Theorem 6.19 ensures that
the class
of
-nested
numbers forms a surreal substructure, so
can
uniquely be written as
for some surreal
parameter
.
One may wonder whether it could happen that . In other words: do there exist pre-nested numbers
that are not nested? For this, let us now describe an example of an
admissible sequence
such that the class
of
-nested
numbers contains a smallest element
.
This number
is pre-nested, but cannot be nested
by Theorem 6.19. Note that our example is
“transserial” in the sense that it does not involve any
hyperexponentials.
Example be a nested sequence with
. Let
be the simplest
-nested number. We define a coding
sequence
by
Note that
where is an infinite monomial, so
is
-nested. In
particular, the sequence
is admissible.
Assume for contradiction that there is a -nested
number
with
.
Since
, we have
. Recall that
and
are purely large, so
.
In particular
which contradicts the assumption that is
-nested. We deduce that
is the minimum of the class
of
-nested numbers. In view of
Theorem 6.19, the sequence
cannot
be nested.
The above examples shows that there exist admissible sequences that are
not nested. Let us now construct an admissible sequence
such that the class
of
-nested numbers is actually empty.
Example
and set
for all
.
We claim that the coding sequence
is admissible.
In order to see this, let
.
Then
Since is
-admissible
(i.e.
-admissible), we deduce
that
is
-admissible,
whence
is admissible. Assume for contradiction
that
is non-empty, and let
. Then
is
-nested, so
,
whence
: a contradiction.
Traditional transseries in can be regarded as
infinite expressions that involve
,
real constants, infinite summation, exponentiation and logarithms. It is
convenient to regard such expressions as infinite labeled trees. In this
section, we show that surreal numbers can be represented similarly as
infinite expressions in
that also involve
hyperexponentials and hyperlogarithms. One technical difficulty is that
the most straightforward way to do this leads to ambiguities in the case
of nested numbers. These ambiguities can be resolved by associating a
surreal number to every infinite path in the tree. In view of the
results from Section 6, this will enable us to regard any
surreal number as a unique hyperseries in
.
Remark
Let us consider the monomial from Example 5.3. We may recursively expand
as
In order to formalize the general recursive expansion process, it is more convenient to work with the unsimplified version of this expression
Introducing as a notation for the
“power” operator, the above expression may naturally be
rewritten as a tree:
In the next subsection, we will describe a general procedure to expand surreal monomials and numbers as trees.
In what follows, a tree is a set of
nodes
together with a function that associates
to each node
an arity
and a sequence
of children; we write
for the set of children of
. Moreover, we assume that
contains a special element
,
called the root of
,
such that for any
there exist a unique
(called the height of
and
also denoted by
) and unique
nodes
with
,
, and
for
. The height
of the tree
is the maximum of the
heights of all nodes; we set
if there exist
nodes of arbitrarily large heights.
Given a class , an
-labeled tree is a tree
together with a map
, called
the labeling. Our final objective is to express numbers using
-labeled trees, where
Instead of computing such expressions in a top-down manner (from the
leaves until the root), we will compute them in a bottom-up fashion
(from the root until the leaves). For this purpose, it is convenient to
introduce a separate formal symbol for every
, together with the extended
signature
We use as a placeholder for a tree expression
for
whose determination is postponed to a later
stage.
Consider a -labeled tree
and a map
.
We say that
is an evaluation of
if for each node
one of the
following statements holds:
, the family
is well based and
;
,
, and
;
,
,
,
and
;
,
, and
;
,
, and
;
We call the value of
via
. We say that
is a value of
if there
exists an evaluation of
with
.
Proof. This is straightforward, by applying the
rules E1–E7
recursively (from the leaves to the root in the case of (a)
and the other way around for (b)).
Although evaluations with a given end-value are unique for a fixed tree
, different trees may produce
the same value. Our next aim is to describe a standard way to expand
numbers using trees. Let us first consider the case of a monomial
. If
,
then the standard monomial expansion of
is the
-labeled tree
with
and
. Otherwise, we may write
with
or
.
Depending on whether
or
, we respectively take
and call the standard monomial
expansion of
. Let us
next consider a general number
and let
be the ordinal size of its support. Then we may write
for a sequence
and a
-decreasing sequence
. For each
,
let
be the standard monomial expansion of
. Then we define the
-labeled tree
and call it the standard expansion of . Note that the height of
is
at most
, there exists a
unique evaluation
of
, and
.
Now consider two trees and
with respective labelings
and
. We say that
refines
if
and
there exist evaluations
and
such that
for all
and
whenever
.
Now assume that
for some evaluation
. Then we say that
is a
tree expansion of
if for every
with
, the
subtree
of
with root
refines the standard expansion of
. In particular, a tree expansion
of a number
with
always refines the standard expansion of
.
Proof. Given ,
we say that an
-labeled tree
is
-settled
if
for all nodes
of
height
. Let us show how to
construct a sequence
of
-labeled tree expansions of
such that the following statements hold for each
:
We will write for the labeling of
.
We take such that
and
. Setting
, the conditions S1,
S2, S3, and
S4 are naturally satisfied.
Assume now that has been constructed and let us
show how to construct
. Let
be the subset of
of
nodes
of level
with
. Given
, let
be the standard
expansion of
and let
be
the unique evaluation of
. We
define
to be the tree that is obtained from
when replacing each node
by
the tree
.
Since each tree is of height at most
, the height of
is finite. Since
is clearly
-settled, this proves S1.
We define an evaluation
by setting
for any
and
for any
and
(note that
is well defined since
for all
). We have
, so S2
holds for
. By construction,
and the evaluations
and
coincide on
;
this proves S3. Finally, let
be a tree expansion of
with labels
in
and let
be the unique
evaluation of
with
.
Then
refines
,
so
coincides with
on
. Let
. Since
is a tree expansion
of
, the subtree
of
with root
refines
, whence
. Moreover,
,
so
coincides with
on
. Altogether, this shows that
refines
.
Having completed the construction of our sequence, we next define a
-labeled tree
and a map
by taking
and by setting
and
for any
and
such that
. By construction,
we have
and
refines
for every
.
We claim that is a tree expansion of
. Indeed, consider a node
of height
with
. Then
and
, since
is
-settled. Consequently, the subtree of
with root
refines the
standard expansion of
. Since
refines
,
it follows that the subtree of
with root
also refines the standard expansion of
. This completes the proof of our claim.
It remains to show that is the unique tree
expansion of
with labels in
. So let
be any tree
expansion of
with labeling
. For every
,
it follows from S4 that
. Moreover, since
is
-settled,
coincides with both
and
on those nodes in
that are of height
. Consequently,
and
coincides with
on
. Since every node in
has finite height, we conclude that
.
From now on, we only consider tree expansions with labels in , as in Lemma 7.3.
Given a class
of nested numbers as in Section 6, it can be verified that every element in
has the same tree expansion. We still need a notational way to
distinguish numbers with the same expansion.
Let be a pre-nested number. By Theorem 6.15,
we get a smallest
such that
is nested. Hence
for the class
of
-nested numbers. Theorem
6.19 implies that there exists a unique number
with
. We call
the nested rank of
and write
. By Corollary 6.23, we note that
for all
. Given an arbitrary infinite path
in a number
,
there exists a
such that
has no bad indices for
(modulo a further
increase of
, we may even
assume
to be nested). Let
. We call
the nested
rank of
, where we note
that the value of
does not depend on the choice
of
.
Let be the tree expansion of a number
and let
be the evaluation with
. An infinite path
in
is a sequence
of
nodes in
with
and
for all
.
Such a path induces an infinite path
in
: let
be
the indices with
; then we
take
for each
.
It is easily verified that this induces a one-to-one correspondence
between the infinite paths in
and the infinite
paths in
. We call
the nested rank of the infinite path
in
. Denoting
by
the set of all infinite paths in
, we thus have a map
. We call
the
hyperserial description of
.
We are now in a position to prove the final theorem of this paper.
Proof of Theorem 1.3
with the
same hyperserial description
and let
be the evaluations of
with
and
. We
need to prove that
. Assume
for contradiction that
. We
define an infinite path
in
with
for all
by setting
and
,
where
is minimal such that
. (Note that such a number
indeed exists, since otherwise
using the rules
E1–E7.)
This infinite path also induces infinite paths
and
in
and
with
and
for a certain sequence
and all
. Let
be such that
and
have no bad indices for
and
.
The way we chose
ensures that the coding
sequences associated to the paths
and
coincide, so they induce the same nested surreal
substructure
. It follows
that
, which contradicts our
assumptions. We conclude that
and
must be equal.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. Asymptotic Differential Algebra and Model Theory of Transseries. Number 195 in Annals of Mathematics studies. Princeton University Press, 2017.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. On numbers, germs, and transseries. In Proc. Int. Cong. of Math. 2018, volume 2, pages 19–42. Rio de Janeiro, 2018.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der
Hoeven. Hardy fields, the intermediate value property, and -freeness. In F. Delon, M.
Dickmann, D. Gondard, and T. Servi, editors, Structures
algébriques ordonnées, séminaire
2017–18, volume 93 of Prépublications de
l'équipe de logique mathématique de
l'Université Paris Diderot. 2019.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der
Hoeven. The surreal numbers as a universal -field. J. Eur. Math. Soc.,
21(4):1179–1199, 2019.
V. Bagayoko and J. van der Hoeven. Surreal substructures. HAL-02151377 (pre-print), 2019.
V. Bagayoko and J. van der Hoeven. The hyperserial field of surreal numbers. Technical Report, HAL, 2021. https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-03232836.
V. Bagayoko, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Hyperserial fields. (notes non publiées), 2020.
V. Bagayoko, J. van der Hoeven, and V. Mantova. Defining a surreal hyperexponential. Technical Report, HAL, 2020. https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02861485.
A. Berarducci. Surreal numbers, exponentiation and derivations. https://arxiv.org/abs/2008.06878, 08 2020.
A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Surreal numbers, derivations and transseries. JEMS, 20(2):339–390, 2018.
A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Transseries as germs of surreal functions. Trans. of the AMS, 371:3549–3592, 2019.
N. Bourbaki. Fonctions d'une variable réelle. Éléments de Mathématiques (Chap. 5). Hermann, 2-nd edition, 1961.
G. Cantor. Sur les fondements de la théorie des ensembles transfinis. Jacques Gabay, 1899. Reprint from les Mémoires de la Société des Sciences physiques et naturelles de Bordeaux.
B. Dahn and P. Göring. Notes on exponential-logarithmic terms. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 127(1):45–50, 1987.
L. van den Dries and Ph. Ehrlich. Fields of surreal numbers and exponentiation. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 167(2):173–188, 2001.
L. van den Dries, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Logarithmic hyperseries. Trans. of the AMS, 372(7):5199–5241, 2019.
L. van den Dries, A. Macintyre, and D. Marker. Logarithmic-exponential series. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 111(1-2):61–113, 2001.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Sur la grandeur relative des infinis des fonctions. Annali di Matematica Pura ed Applicata (1867-1897), 4(1):338–353, 1870.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über asymptotische Werte, infinitäre Approximationen und infinitäre Auflösung von Gleichungen. Math. Ann., 8:363–414, 1875.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über die Paradoxen des Infinitärscalcüls. Math. Ann., 11:149–167, 1877.
J. Écalle. Introduction aux fonctions analysables et preuve constructive de la conjecture de Dulac. Hermann, collection: Actualités mathématiques, 1992.
J. Ecalle. The natural growth scale. Journal of the European Mathematical Society, CARMA, vol 1:93–223, 2016.
U. Felgner. Die Hausdorffsche Theorie der -Mengen und ihre
Wirkungsgeschichte. In Springer-Verlag, editor, Felix
Hausdorff
G. Fisher. The infinite and infinitesimal quantities of du Bois-Reymond and their reception. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci., 24:101–163, 1981.
H. Gonshor. An Introduction to the Theory of Surreal Numbers. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1986.
H. Hahn. Über die nichtarchimedischen Größensysteme. Sitz. Akad. Wiss. Wien, 116:601–655, 1907.
G. H. Hardy. Orders of infinity, the 'Infinitärcalcül' of Paul du Bois-Reymond. Cambridge University Press edition, 1910.
G. H. Hardy. Properties of logarithmico-exponential functions. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, s2-10(1):54–90, 1912.
J. van der Hoeven. Automatic asymptotics. PhD thesis, École polytechnique, Palaiseau, France, 1997.
J. van der Hoeven. Transséries fortement monotones. Chapter 1 of unpublished CNRS activity report, https://www.texmacs.org/joris/schmeling/rap1-2000.pdf, 2000.
J. van der Hoeven. Transseries and real differential algebra, volume 1888 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, 2006.
H. Kneser. Reelle analytische Lösungen der
Gleichung und verwandter
Funktionalgleichungen. Jour. f. d. reine und angewandte
Math., 187(1/2):56–67, 1950.
D. Lemire. Nombres surreels: decompositions de la forme normale, extrema, sommes infinies et fonctions d'ensembles. PhD thesis, Université de Montréal, 1996.
D. Lemire. Décompositions successives de la
forme normale d'un surréel et
généralisation des -nombres.
Ann. Sci. Math. Québec, 21(2):133–146, 1997.
D. Lemire. Remarques sur les surréels dont la forme normale se décompose indéfiniment. Ann. Sci. Math. Québec, 23(1):73–85, 1999.
V. Mantova and M. Matusinski. Surreal numbers with derivation, Hardy fields and transseries: a survey. Contemporary Mathematics, pages 265–290, 2017.
M. C. Schmeling. Corps de transséries. PhD thesis, Université Paris-VII, 2001.
admissible number 33
admissible sequence 34
-atomic number
11
bad index 21
Cantor normal form 10
coding sequence 31
coefficient of an ordinal 10
cofinal with respect to 13
cut equation 13
cut representation 13
dominant monomial 7
exponent of an ordinal 10
function group 14
functional equation 11
good index 21
good path, bad path 22
hyperexponential 11
hyperlogarithm 11
infinitesimal series 8
left option, right option 13
logarithm 11
logarithmic hyperseries 8
nested number 35
nested sequence 36
path 21
positive infinite series 8
purely large series 8
-simple element 14
subpath 22
surreal substructure 12
tail-atomic number 17
term 7
-truncated series 11
truncation 7
uniform equation 13
well-based family 8
well-nested number 22
field of well-based series with real
coefficients over
7
support of a series 7
set of terms of a series
7
truncation
of
7
and
7
and
8
series
with
8
series
with
8
series
with
and
8
field of logarithmic hyperseries 8
group of logarithmic hypermonomials of force
8
field of logarithmic hyperseries of force
9
unique series in
with
9
class of ordinals 9
simplicity relation 9
ordinal sum of
and
10
ordinal product of
and
10
ordinal exponentiation with base
at
10
for each exponent
of
10
for each exponent
of
10
for all
10
if
is a successor and
if
is a limit 10
for
10
composition law
10
class of
-truncated
series 12
-maximal
-truncated truncation of
12
class of numbers
with
14
class of
-simple
elements 14
projection
14
comparison between sets of strictly
increasing bijections 14
and
are mutually pointwise cofinal 14
function group generated by
14
translation
15
homothety
15
power function
15
function group
15
function group
15
function group
15
function group
15
function group
15
value
of the path
at
21
dominant monomial of
21
constant coefficient of
21
length of a path
21
concatenation of paths
22
Berarducci and Mantova's nested truncation
relation 24
class of admissible numbers
34
class of
-admissible
numbers 34
class of
-nested
numbers 35
class of
-nested
numbers 35