|
Abstract
Transseries provide a universal framework for the formal asymptotics of regular solutions to ordinary differential equations at infinity. More general functional equations such as may have solutions that grow faster than any iterated exponential and thereby faster than any transseries.
In order to develop a truly universal framework for the asymptotics of regular univariate functions at infinity, we therefore need a generalization of transseries: hyperseries. Hyperexponentials and hyperlogarithms play a central role in such a program. The first non-trivial hyperexponential and hyperlogarithm are and its functional inverse , where satisfies the above equation. Formally, such functions and can be introduced for any ordinal . For instance, , , , and satisfies .
In the present work, we construct a field of hyperseries that is closed under and for all ordinals . This generalizes previous work by Schmeling [29] in the case when , as well as the previous construction of the field of logarithmic hyperseries by van den Dries, van der Hoeven, and Kaplan [12].
In order to get our hands on a complex mathematical expression, we first need to simplify it as much as possible. This can often be achieved by eliminating parts that are asymptotically negligible. For instance, when studying the expression for large values of , we may compute the approximations , , and then . Such approximations rely on our ability to determine and compare asymptotic rates of growth.
Is it possible to develop a universal framework for this kind of asymptotic simplification? This sounds like a difficult problem in general, especially for multivariate functions or functions with an irregular growth like . On the other hand, the problem might become tractable for univariate functions in a neighborhood of infinity , provided that is constructed using a limited number of well-behaved primitives.
An important first step towards a systematic asymptotic calculus of this kind was made by Hardy in [20, 21], based on earlier ideas by du Bois-Reymond [14, 15, 16]. We say that is an -function if it is constructed from and the real numbers using the field operations, exponentiation, and logarithms. Given two non-zero germs of -functions , at infinity, Hardy proved that exactly one of the relations , , or holds, where
Hardy also observed [20, p. 22] that “The only scales of infinity that are of any practical importance in analysis are those which may be constructed by means of the logarithmic and exponential functions.” In other words, Hardy suggested that the framework of -functions not only allows for the development of a systematic asymptotic calculus, but that this framework is also sufficient for all “practical” purposes.
Hardy went on [20, chapter V] with the examination of possible counterexamples, through the exploration of pathological functions whose asymptotic behavior does not conform to any logarithmico-exponential scale. Here he made a distinction between irregular asymptotic behavior (such as oscillating functions) and regular asymptotic behavior that yet cannot be described in terms of -functions. Basic examples of the second type were already constructed by du Bois-Reymond and Hardy [20, chapter II]. For instance, let for and let for each . Then grows faster than any -function.
In order to formalize the concept of “regular” growth at infinity, we focus on classes of (germs of) functions that are stable under common calculus operations such as addition, multiplication, differentiation, and composition. The class of -functions indeed satisfies these conditions, but it is interesting to investigate whether there exist larger classes of functions with similar properties.
Two particular settings that have received a lot of attention are Hardy fields (i.e. fields of germs of real continuously differentiable functions at infinity that are closed under differentiation [7]) and germs of definable functions in -minimal structures [10]. Each of these settings excludes oscillatory behavior in a strong sense. For instance, although the function does not oscillate for large values of , its second derivative does, so the germ of this function at infinity does not belong to a Hardy field.
With a more precise definition of regularity at hand, one may re-examine the existence of regular functions whose asymptotic growth falls outside any scale of -functions. For instance, the function from above is not even continuous and thereby not sufficiently regular. Nevertheless, it was shown by Kneser [28] that the functional equation
has a real analytic solution on . This provides us with a more natural candidate for a regular function that grows faster than any -function. Indeed, it was shown by Boshernitzan [6] that Kneser's solution belongs to a Hardy field. The functional inverse of frequently occurs in the complexity analysis of recursive algorithms that use exponential size reductions. For instance, the fastest known algorithm [22] for multiplying two polynomials of degree in runs in time . This shows that Hardy's framework of -functions is insufficient, even for practical purposes.
Another example of a regular function that is not asymptotic to any -function is the functional inverse of . This fact was actually raised as a question by Hardy and only proved in [23] and [13]. More explicit examples of such functions, like , were given in [23]. It turns out that the class of -functions lacks several important closure properties (e.g. functional inversion and integration), which makes it unsuitable as a universal framework for asymptotic calculus.
The class of transseries forms a better candidate for such a universal framework. A transseries is a formal object that is constructed from (with ) and the real numbers, using exponentiation, logarithms, and infinite sums. One example of a transseries is
Depending on conditions satisfied by their supports, there are different types of transseries. The first constructions of fields of transseries are due to Dahn and Göring [9] and Écalle [17]. More general constructions were proposed subsequently by van der Hoeven and his student Schmeling [23, 29].
Transseries form a natural “infinitary” extension of the concept of an -function. The transseries are closed under integration and functional inversion [23, 13]. They also satisfy a differential intermediate value property [26, Chapter 9]. However, transseries are only defined formally, so their analytic meaning is not necessarily obvious. One technique for associating an analytic meaning to certain divergent transseries is accelero-summation [17], a generalization of Borel summation [5]. An alternative technique is based on differential algebra and model theory [27, 1]. In this paper, we focus on formal asymptotic computations, without worrying about analytic counterparts.
Despite the excellent closure properties of transseries for the resolution of differential equations, the functional equation (1.1) still does not have a transseries solution. In order to establish a universal formal framework for asymptotic calculus, we therefore need to incorporate extremely fast growing functions such as , as well as formal solutions , , etc. to the following equations:
The fast growing functions , , are called hyperexponentials. Their functional inverses , , are called hyperlogarithms and they grow extremely slowly. The first construction of a field of generalized transseries that is closed under and for all was accomplished in [29]. Here we understand that and .
The hyperlogarithms , , etc. obviously satisfy the functional equations
In addition, we have a simple formula for their derivatives
where and
for all and . The formula (1.4) is eligible for generalization to arbitrary ordinals . Taking , we note that the function does not satisfy any functional equation. Yet any truly universal formal framework for asymptotic calculus should accommodate functions such as for the simple reason that it is possible to construct models with good properties in which they exist. For instance, by [6], there exist Hardy fields with infinitely large functions that grow more slowly than for all .
The construction of the field of logarithmic hyperseries in [12] was the first step towards the incorporation of hyperlogarithms with arbitrary . The field is the smallest non-trivial field of generalized power series over that is closed under all hyperlogarithms and infinite real power products. It turns out that is a proper class and that is closed under differentiation, integration, and composition.
The main purpose of the present paper is the construction of a field of general hyperseries that is also closed under the functional inverse of for every ordinal . Our construction strongly relies on properties of the field of logarithmic hyperseries. Intuitively speaking, the reason is that the derivative of can be expressed as the composition of a logarithmic hyperseries with :
and similarly for all higher derivatives. One key aspect of our approach is therefore to construct increasingly large fields of hyperseries simultaneously with compositions
where denotes the class of positive infinitely large elements of .
The main result of this paper is the construction of a field of hyperseries that is closed under all hyperlogarithms and all hyperexponentials . Does this end our quest for a universal formal framework for asymptotic calculus? Not quite yet. First of all, it remains to be shown that is closed under all common calculus operations, such as differentiation and composition. Secondly, the field does not contain any solution to the functional equation
Fortunately, it is possible to construct fields of transseries with “nested” solutions
to such equations [29, Section 2.5]. Something similar is possible for hyperseries; although this is beyond the scope of the present paper, we introduce the fundamental concepts that we expect to use for this generalization.
One may also wonder whether there exist natural models for hyperexponential functions and hyperseries. We already noted that Kneser constructed a real analytic solution of the equation (1.1). Schmeling also constructed real analytic solutions , , of (1.2), (1.3), etc. Écalle introduced a systematic technique for the construction of quasi-analytic solutions to these and more general iteration equations [17]. In general, it seems unlikely that there exist any “privileged” regular solutions at infinity.
Another interesting model for hyperexponentiation is Conway's field of surreal numbers [8]. The field is a non-standard extension of the field which contains the class of ordinal numbers. The arithmetic operations are defined in a surprisingly “simple” way, using transfinite induction. Nevertheless, the field has a remarkably rich structure; e.g. it is real-closed. The exponential function on the reals has been extended to by Gonshor [18] and this extension preserves the first order properties of [11].
A “simplest” surreal solution to (1.1) with good properties has been constructed in [3]. This solution is only defined on , but in view of our previous remarks on real solutions of (1.1), is interesting to note that we may indeed consider it as “the” privileged solution on . Constructing each hyperlogarithm and hyperexponential on surreal numbers involves overcoming many technical difficulties. Our results from this paper reduce this to the simpler task of defining partial hyperlogarithms on , which satisfy a short list of axioms.
We finally note that Berarducci and Mantova also defined a derivation with respect to on [4]. This derivation again has good model theoretic properties [2]. However, although the derivation satisfies for all , it was pointed out in [1] that it does not satisfy for all , for “reasonable” definitions of . Indeed, for the definition of from [3], we have .
Stated differently, the hyperexponential structure on reveals that is not the ultimate derivation on with respect to that we might hope for. One major motivation behind the work in this paper is precisely the construction of a better derivation on , as well as a composition. The plan, which has been detailed in [1], is to construct an isomorphism between and a suitable field of hyperseries with a natural derivation and composition with respect to . The present paper can be regarded as one important step in this direction.
In order to construct a field of hyperseries that is closed under all hyperexponentials and all hyperlogarithms , we follow the common approach of starting with an arbitrary field of hyperseries and then closing it off via a transfinite sequence of extensions.
Now closing off under hyperlogarithms turns out to be much easier than closing off under hyperexponentiation. For this reason, and following [23, 29, 12], it is actually convenient to do this once and for all and only work with fields of hyperseries that are already closed under all hyperlogarithms. In particular, the smallest field of hyperseries of this type with an element is the field of logarithmic hyperseries from [12], where for all .
The next step is to work out the technical definition of a “field of hyperseries” that will be suitable for the hyperexponential extension process. Quite naturally, such a field should be a Hahn field of generalized power series, where is a totally ordered monomial group: see Subsection 2.2 for basic definitions and reminders. For reasons mentioned in the previous subsection, we also require the existence of a composition law , where . For each , this allows us to define a function by setting for .
We say that is a hyperserial field if
the composition satisfies a list of natural
axioms such as associativity and restricted Taylor expansions; see
Section 6 for the full list of axioms. The only non-obvious
axiom for traditional fields of transseries states that a transseries
is a monomial if and only if
(i.e. the support of only contains
infinitely large elements). The only non-obvious axiom
Our definition of hyperserial fields is similar to the definition of fields of transseries from [24, 29], with a few differences. The old definition includes an additional axiom of well-nestedness T4 which is important for the definition of derivations and compositions, but which is not required for the purposes of the present paper. Of course, our current presentation is based on the composition law . Finally, we use a slightly different technical notion of confluence. We say that is confluent if, for all ordinals and all , there exist a -atomic element and with . We refer to Remark 3.6 for a discussion of the differences with the definition from [29].
Given an ordinal , it turns out that the hyperlogarithm is entirely determined by its restriction to the set of -atomic elements. The field together with these restricted hyperlogarithms is called the hyperserial skeleton of . The fact that the logarithm can be recovered from its restriction to is a well-known fact. Indeed, we first recover on , since and for all . For all , , and infinitesimal , we then have
Hyperserial skeletons can also be defined in an abstract manner, i.e. without knowledge of a hyperserial field of which it is the skeleton. Precise definitions will be given in Section 3; for now it suffices to know that an abstract hyperserial skeleton is a field of generalized power series together with partially defined functions that satisfy suitable axioms. The first key result of this paper is the construction of an exact correspondence between abstract hyperserial skeletons and hyperserial fields. This correspondence preserves confluence for a suitable analogue of the confluence axiom for hyperserial skeletons.
Sections 4 and 5 contain the core of this construction. In Section 4, we first show how to extend the partial functions of a confluent hyperserial skeleton to all of . In Section 5, we prove that any confluent hyperserial skeleton can be endowed with a well-behaved composition law . In Section 6, we complete our construction of a correspondence between hyperserial skeletons and hyperserial fields. More precisely, we prove:
Theorem
Theorem
Sections 7 and 8 are devoted to the closure of a confluent hyperserial field under hyperexponentiation. In view of Theorem 1.1, it suffices to operate on the level of hyperserial skeletons instead of hyperserial fields. In Section 7, we investigate when the hyperexponential of an element in already exists in . This gives us a criterion under which the extended hyperlogarithms are bijective. In Section 8, we prove our main theorem that every confluent hyperserial skeleton has a minimal extension whose extended hyperlogarithm functions are bijective:
Theorem
is bijective for each ordinal . Moreover, if is another confluent extension and if the extended function is bijective for each , then there is a unique embedding of into over .
Corollary. There exists a minimal hyperserial extension of that is closed under for all ordinals .
We work in von Neumann-Gdel-Bernays set theory with Global Choice (NBG), which is a conservative extension of ZFC. In this set theory, all proper classes are in bijective correspondence with the class of all ordinal numbers. We will sometimes write for elements that are either ordinals or equal to the class of ordinals. In that case, we write instead of . We make the convention that . If is a successor ordinal, then we define to be the unique ordinal with . If is a limit ordinal, then we define .
Recall that every ordinal has a unique Cantor normal form
where , and with . The ordinals are called the exponents of the Cantor normal form and the integers its coefficients. We write (resp. ) if each exponent of the Cantor normal form of satisfies (resp. ). We also define to be the unique ordinal with and with for some . Note that if and only if .
is a well-based set, i.e. a set which is well-ordered for the reverse order .
We regard elements of as well-based series where for each . By [19], the class is a field for the operations
Note that each sum has finite support. We say that is a field of well-based series and that is the monomial group of . An element is called a monomial.
An increasing union of fields of well-based series is not, in general, a field of well-based series. However, this is always true if the union is indexed over :
Lemma
Proof. Set . Clearly, , so it remains to show the other inclusion. Let . For each , let be the least with . Set
Then .
to be the dominant monomial of . We give the structure of a totally ordered field by setting
We define the asymptotic relations , , , and on by
The monomial group is naturally embedded in as an ordered group and
for all non-zero .
For and , we set . We say that a series is a truncation of , denoted , if there is with . We have if and only if (which holds vacuously when ). We finally define
Series in are called infinitesimal and series in are called positive infinite. Each can be decomposed uniquely as , where , , and is infinitesimal.
is a well-based set, and
is finite for all .
Then we may define the sum of as the series
If and are families, then we define their product as the family . By [25, Proposition 3.3], if and are well-based, then so is their product, and we have
We will frequently use the following facts regarding families for and .
Lemma
Let be another field of well-based series. If is -linear, then we say that is strongly linear if for every well-based family in 𝕋, the family in is well-based, and
If is a function, then we say that it is well-based if for any well-based family in , the family in is well-based. Then extends uniquely into a strongly linear map [25, Proposition 3.5]. Moreover, is strictly increasing whenever is strictly increasing and it is a ring morphism whenever for all [25, Corollary 3.8]. In particular, if for all and is strictly increasing, then is well-based. Hence:
Proposition
If extends (so extends ), then the operator support of a function is the set . If is a well-based set, then is well-based; see [12, Lemma 2.9].
Definition
is well-based.
Proposition
Proof. Given a well-based subset , we have to show that is a well-based family. We have
so is a well-based subset of . For any , the set of pairs with forms a finite antichain. Since any with induces such a pair , it follows that the set of all such is also finite. This completes the proof that is well-based. To see that is injective, let and take with . The assumption that is strictly increasing gives , whence .
(2.1) |
and for where , , and , we set .
Proposition
Proof. For , the first two relations follow from basic power series manipulations; see [25, Corollary 16]. The extension to the general case when is straightforward and left to the reader.
Assume now that and . Since , it suffices to show that . Write where , , and . Since , we have , so either , or and , or and . If , then , so . If and , then and . If and , then , so .
Thus, the extended real power operation gives the structure of a multiplicative ordered -vector space. Accordingly, we say that has real powers.
and elements , we say that is defined at if the family is well-based.
Lemma
Proof. We prove this by induction on . If , then set and write . Suppose that and let be the set of with . Fix and let be such that for all . Since , there exists an index with . Then , whence
In particular, is countable, whereas is uncountable, so .
Now suppose that and write . Assume that . By the induction hypothesis, we can find and such that . Fix such elements and let be the set of such that . By the special case when , we see that . Thus, for some .
A central object in our work is the field of logarithmic hyperseries of [12], equipped with its natural derivation and composition . We briefly recall its definition and some of its properties.
We call the field of logarithmic hyperseries of strength . If are ordinals with , then we let denote the interval and we let denote the subgroup
As in [12], we write , and
We will sometimes write and . We have natural inclusions , which give natural inclusions .
where . Note that . For and , we sometimes write . Equipped with its derivation, the field is an -field with small derivation, so for , we have
Moreover, is well-based, which implies the following variant of [12, Lemma 2.13]:
Lemma
Proof. Since is well-based and is a strongly linear field embedding, the set is well-based. Thus is well-based and , since . Let . For each , we have
Since is well-based and , it follows that is well-based and that the map is well-defined and strongly linear. For all , we also have
which shows that preserves multiplication.
For , the map is a strongly linear field embedding. As a consequence this map preserves the relations and [12, Lemma 6.6].
For and , we have [12, Proposition 7.14].
For and , we have [12, Corollary 7.5].
For and , we have and [12, Section 1.4].
For ordinals , we have [12, Corollary 5.11].
For any successor ordinal , we have [12, Lemma 5.8].
The constant term of vanishes if is a limit ordinal [12, Lemma 5.8].
For and with , the family is well-based, and
[12, Proposition 8.1] |
The uniqueness follows from [12, Theorem 1.3]. By [12, Proposition 7.8], the derivation also satisfies the chain rule: for all and , we have
As we will see, the field equipped with the composition is hyperserial.
For , the unique composition from above restricts to a composition . For , the map defined by is a strongly linear field embedding with image by [12, Lemma 5.13]. Accordingly, for , we let denote the unique series in with . Note that for all and that, more generally, for and . For and we have
(2.2) |
where is the derivation on (see [12, Section 5.1]). Let . Then is strongly linear and , so, by [12, Lemma 2.2],
(2.3) |
In particular,
(2.4) |
Lemma
Proof. Since is closed under taking derivatives and the derivation preserves infinitesimals, it suffices to prove the lemma for . We have , so
Since and , this yields . Since as well, we have . Since the map maps onto , we conclude that .
We let be an ordered field of well-based series with real powers. Let be an ordinal with . Given a structure where are partial functions on , we consider the following axioms for :
Suppose satisfies all axioms
(3.1) |
For , we call the class of -atomic elements. Note that for all . We let be the identity function with and, for with Cantor normal form , we define . Here we understand that whenever , , and so on until .
Proposition
Proof. Given and , let us first show by induction on that is defined and in . This holds for by definition. Let and assume that the assertion holds strictly below . If , then . Assume and let , and be such that . We have so by definition. In particular , so our inductive hypothesis on applied to gives that is a monomial.
Given such that and for all , let us next show by induction that . This is clear if . Let be such that the statement holds strictly below . If is a successor, then for and , we have so for all , whence . Assume now that is a limit and let . Then for all , so the induction hypothesis yields . We again conclude that .
Let be an ordered field of well-based series
with real powers, let , and
let be partial functions
on which satisfy the axioms
We define a logarithm as follows:
(3.2) |
Then is an ordered -vector subspace of . For with , we consider the following axiom:
Remark
Definition
Note that a hyperserial skeleton of force 0 is just a field of well-based series with real powers and that is a hyperserial skeleton of force if and only if is a hyperserial skeleton of force for each ordinal . We will often write to denote a hyperserial skeleton (of force ), where it is implied that for , the term refers to the -th hyperlogarithm on .
Definition
and such that
If is an embedding of force , then we say that is an extension of of force .
In this subsection, let be a hyperserial skeleton of force and let with . We inductively define the notion of -confluence in conjunction with functions and the classes , as follows:
Definition
Let with , let , and suppose is -confluent for all .
If is a successor, then we define to be the class of series with
for some .
If is a limit, then we define to be the class of series with
for some .
If each class contains an -atomic element, then we say that is -confluent. We will see that each class contains at most one -atomic element, which we denote by .
Remark
Lemma
Proof. We prove this by induction on , noticing that the case is trivial. Assume that this is the case for all ordinals and let . To see that is well-defined, let with . We need to show .
Assume that is a successor. Take with Since is -atomic for each and since is well-defined by our induction hypothesis, we have for each . It follows by induction on that for each and, likewise, for each , so . As both and are monomials, we have . The axiom implies that is injective and thus .
Assume now that is a limit and take with . Since is -atomic and since is well-defined by our induction hypothesis, we have . Likewise, , so . As both and are monomials, we have . Since is injective by , we conclude that .
As to our second assertion, consider and with . If is a successor, then the inductive hypothesis implies , so and . If is a limit, then , so and .
Corollary
Proposition
Proof. We prove this by induction on . Let .
It is clear that is convex and that is increasing. Let and assume that
the result holds for all . By
the monotonicity axioms, each function is
strictly increasing on (when , one also needs to use
If is -confluent for all , then the proposition implies that the classes with form a partition of into convex subclasses. If is also -confluent, then we have the following explicit decomposition for all :
Definition
Note that if , then 𝕋 is confluent if and only if it is -confluent.
Let be an ordinal and set . The goal of this section is to check that is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force . This is immediate for , so we assume that .
Definition
We will show that is a hyperserial skeleton by checking that the axioms are satisfied. We begin with the domain of definition axioms.
Lemma
Proof. We prove this by induction on . The case when is immediate. For , consider an infinite monomial . We have , which is a monomial if and only for some . Conversely, for each we have . Now let and suppose that the lemma holds for all non-zero ordinals less than . Assume that is a limit. We have , whence
Assume now that is a successor. If , then where , and we clearly have for all , whence . Conversely, let . Then where . If is a limit, then , whence and . If is a successor, then for some and some , so
Since , we see that
Since , we must have , so .
For and , note that . Note also that the notions of -atomicity and -atomicity coincide in whenever is a limit with . This will not be the case in general.
Proposition
Proof. Let and let . By Remark 3.2, we may assume . We have for some . Let be a sequence of real numbers. We have
This sum coincides with where .
Proposition
Proof. Let and let . We have for some . Write where , , and if is a limit. We claim . If is a successor, then since , we have
If is a limit, then , so
Now we move on to verification of
so
As to
Recall that for and , we write for the real exponent of in . Given , we define to be the least ordinal with ; see also [12, p. 23].
Proposition
(3.3) |
Proof. We first note that is -confluent as is not trivial. We proceed by induction on . Take . If , then we have where is -atomic, so and is -confluent. It remains to note that .
Now suppose that and assume that is -confluent and satisfies (3.3) for all . Suppose is a successor, so . Write with and with if is a limit. We have , so
and .
Now suppose is a limit, so there is with . By hypothesis, we have that and so
Again, this yields .
Theorem
Proof. Using the identity
for , the field is easily seen to satisfy
Corollary
Let . The purpose of the next two sections is to prove the following theorem:
Theorem
We claim that it suffices to prove the theorem in the case when . The case when
can then be proved as follows: let be a
confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
Throughout this section, we fix an ordinal and a hyperserial skeleton of force . We fix also such that is -confluent and we set . We assume that Theorem 4.1 holds for , so we have a unique composition satisfying , , , and . For and , we write . In light of Lemma 2.9, the expression makes sense for each . Our main goal is to prove the following result:
Proposition
We will also prove that satisfies the extension
of
Our extension will heavily depend on Taylor series expansions, so it is
convenient to introduce some notation for that. Let
be such that for all . Let and
with . By Lemma 2.8
and
Note that and . By [25, Corollary 16], we have
(4.1) |
(4.2) |
(4.3) |
Proposition
with
for all , and
extends the natural logarithm on .
For , writing for , , and , we have
Proof. The uniqueness and the fact that is a morphism are proven in [29, Example 2.1.3 and Lemma 2.1.4]. To see that is order-preserving, we need only check that for all . If , then and we have . If and , then we have , since . If , we have , so .
For , we often write in place of . For , we define to be the unique element of with . If , then we sometimes use instead of .
Proposition
Proof. Let , where , , and . If , then , so . If , then . If , then , since , , and . Thus
If , then and . Hence and . If , then is negative and infinite, so .
Remark
Proposition
Proof. First, note that for all
: if , then this is just axiom
(by (4.3)) | |||
(by ()) | |||
Proposition
Proof. For and , we have and . For , we have
So the family is well-based with . The proposition follows, as
Assume now that . Let us revisit the notion of confluence.
Lemma
Proof. We first show that . Take and such that . We have
where . Set , so . We have
where . Thus, .
Now, fix with and set . By and , we have
Lemma 2.9 in conjunction with the fact that gives us that , so .
Proposition
Proof. We fix . Since , we know by Lemma 4.8 that it is enough to show that We proceed by induction on . If , then and
An easy induction on yields for each , whence the result.
Now suppose that . If is a successor, then for each there is some with . By our inductive assumption applied to , we have that for some . By Lemma 4.8, we have and an easy induction on gives us that . Thus, we have that for some . Likewise, for some . By replacing and with and invoking Lemma 4.8, we may assume that . Since , we have . On the other hand, given , if for some , then take some with . By Lemma 4.8, we have , so .
If is a limit, then for each there is with . By our inductive assumption applied to , we have that for some , so by Lemma 4.8. Thus and likewise, for some . By replacing and with and invoking Lemma 4.8, we may assume that . Since , we have . On the other hand, given , if for some , then take some with . By Lemma 4.8, we have , so .
Proposition 4.9 in conjunction with Lemma 4.8 gives us the following corollary:
Corollary
for all . Moreover, if for some and some , then .
Definition
As discussed at the beginning of the section, the series exists in by Lemmas 2.8 and 2.9. To prove Proposition 4.2 all that remains is to show:
Lemma
Proof. Let , , be as in Definition 4.11 and suppose that for some . Set . We need to show that
Without loss of generality, we may assume that . Now
Since , this yields . Let
considered as formal power series and in Then
so it suffices to show that . For each , we have
so for all , and we conclude that by Lemma 2.7.
We end this section with various extensions of the validity of Taylor series expansions and a proof that is strictly increasing on .
Proposition
Proof. By Corollary 4.10, there is some such that . We may write
Note that is -atomic, so . For we have
so for all . It follows that
This concludes the proof.
Lemma
Proof. By applying to for , we have
Arguing as in the proof of Lemma 4.12, it is enough to show that
as power series in . Let . We have
Therefore,
Since , we are done by Lemma 2.7.
Proposition
Proof. Let with . Set . By Lemmas 2.8 and 2.9, the series exists in . We claim that . As by , it suffices to show that
as power series in . But this follows from Lemma 2.7, by noting that the equality holds when evaluated at any element of .
Now set and let , so . By definition of and the above claim, we have
Using , it follows that
By Lemma 4.14, we conclude that
where the last equality follows from the definition of .
Lemma
Then where .
Proof. Set , so . We have
where the first and third equalities follow from the definition of and where the second equality holds by Lemma 4.14.
Lemma
Proof. By induction on , we may assume that is strictly increasing on for all (the case follows from Proposition 4.3). As a composition of strictly increasing functions is strictly increasing, the function is strictly increasing on for all . Given , let us show that . We start with the case when and take with and . Then is infinitesimal and positive by our induction hypothesis. By Lemma 4.16, we have
Since , we have , so .
Now we turn to the case when . Set and and take an ordinal with
Set , so
Repeated applications of (2.4) with in place of gives , so and
Since , we have so . Thus,
. All together, this shows
that . Likewise, we have
. By the monotonicity axiom
Throughout this section, stands for a fixed
ordinal and for a fixed confluent hyperserial
skeleton of force . We let
. Our aim is to construct a
well-behaved external composition that satisfies
Here is a -confluent hyperserial skeleton of force . The field is the field of well-based series of real powers of the variable , with real coefficients.
Lemma
Proof. Let with , and . Note that . Since and are both well-based, we are done.
Given and , the family is well-based by the above lemma, so we may define
One easily verifies that this composition satisfies and . We next prove
Proposition
Proof. Write where , , and . We have , so . We also have
Since by , we only need to show that . Now for some , so
by Proposition 2.6.
Corollary
Proof. We have
where the second equality follows from Proposition 5.2 and the third follows from strong linearity of composition with .
Proposition
Proof. We first handle the case when , where . We have , so
For , we also have , so . Therefore,
Now, Lemma 2.8 gives that the the map is well-based and strongly linear, so for a general , we have
The above results show that satisfies , and . To complete the proof of Theorem 4.1 for , it remains to show uniqueness.
Proposition
Proof. Let be a composition satisfying conditions , , , and Write , where , , and . By strong linearity, it suffices to verify that for any monomial in . Given , the condition implies
We have , so
We have by and by , so . Likewise, , so
For the remainder of this section, we assume that . By the results in Section 4, we have a well-defined extension of to all of for each . Indeed, for and , take with with (so if is a limit). Then we may set .
Given and , we have by that , so we set . Clearly, the map is an embedding of monomial groups which preserves real powers, and by , this embedding is order-preserving as well. For , we set . By Proposition 2.3, we have:
Lemma
By Lemma 2.8
Lemma
Proof. If is a limit ordinal, then the lemma follows from for any ordinal with , so we may assume that is a successor. We prove the lemma by induction on . The lemma is immediate when , so suppose and take and with . Our induction hypothesis yields
Note that and . We claim that
When , this just follows from . When , this is Proposition 4.7 with in place of and in place of . When , this is Definition 4.11 with in place of and in place of . Since and , it remains to show that . Now as series in . Indeed, for , we have
We conclude by Lemma 2.7.
Lemma 5.6 shows that
Lemma
Proof. Suppose is a successor ordinal, so . Then , so is defined. As the maps and are strongly linear, we may assume that is a monomial . Since for , we have
Now suppose that is a limit and that for some . By increasing , we may assume that , so . Then and give
Lemma
for each with .
Proof. Fix with . We first claim that
If is a limit, then take with . Then , so gives
and gives , thereby proving the claim. If is a successor, then take with . By Lemma 5.7 and the fact that , we have
Having proved our claim, let be given and set . Lemma 2.9 yields , whence . If is a limit, then , where is as above. So in both the successor and limit cases, we may apply Lemma 5.8 with in place of to get
This gives
It remains to show that the family is well-based. Since is a well-based family in and is strongly linear, the family is well-based. Since is well-based and infinitesimal, the family is well-based. We conclude that the family is well-based.
Proposition
Proof. We will show the following:
For each , the family is well-based and
The family is well-based and
The proposition follows from (a) and (b), since the union of finitely many well-based families is well-based and is closed under finite sums.
To see why (a) holds, let and note that
Since is well-based, gives that is well-based. We have
Set . We claim that . If , then and
If , then gives
As for (b), let . By Lemma 5.9, there exists a well-based family from such that
The families and are well-based by Lemma 5.6 and the fact that . Since the family is also well-based, it follows that is again well-based. In particular,
is well-based. Now
Since and are infinitesimal for all , we may write
where By (4.1), we have . Furthermore, P implies
We conclude that .
Let . In light of Proposition 5.10, we define
We note that the map is an embedding of ordered multiplicative groups for each .
Our next objective is to show that the map
extends by strong linearity to a map which
satisfies
Proposition
Proof. Let be the restriction of to and for , let be the restriction of to . Since
it suffices to show that each and are relatively well-based. For the , fix . Our induction hypothesis implies that the map is relatively well-based. By Lemma 5.8 with in place of , we have
It follows that is also relatively well-based with .
Now for . Let . By Lemma 5.9, we have a well-based family from such that
Exponentiating both sides, we obtain
so . The set
is well-based, infinitesimal and does not depend on . Since
for all , we conclude that is well-based.
We already noted that the map from Proposition
5.11 is an order-preserving multiplicative embedding. By
Proposition 2.5, it follows that is
well-based, so it extends uniquely into an order-preserving and strongly
linear embedding . Taking
for all ,
this proves
Proposition
Proof. As in Proposition 5.2, it suffices to prove that holds for each . For such , we have
By Proposition 4.6, we also have . By injectivity of the logarithm, we conclude that .
Lemma
Proof. First, we note that for , we have
where the last equality uses the definition of . Now, let and write with , , and . Then and
Here we used the facts that and that composition with commutes with powers and infinite sums.
Proposition
Proof. We will show by induction on that for all , all , and all . If , then this follows from Proposition 5.12 and strong linearity.
Let , let and be fixed, and assume that the proposition holds whenever for some . By strong linearity, it suffices to prove that for all . Lemma 5.13 gives
Using the injectivity of and strong linearity, we may thus reduce to the case when for . Our induction hypothesis takes care of the case when is a limit ordinal or when , so we may assume that , where . By the inductive definitions of and , we may further reduce to the case when . Lemma 5.13 takes care of the case , so we may assume that . In summary, we thus need to show that , where .
Set . We claim that . We have , where , , and if is a limit ordinal. As , we have
This gives
where the first equality in the second line follows from Proposition 4.13.
Having proved our claim, let us now show that . Take with , and . We have
As and for all , by Lemma 2.9, our induction hypothesis applied to gives
for . Along with
Using also our claim that , we obtain
It remains to show that . Now
so and . We may thus apply Lemma 4.16 to and , to conclude that .
Proposition
Proof. Since holds for , we need only consider the case when is a successor and . We prove the result by induction on . By Proposition 4.7 (when ) or Proposition 4.15 (when ), we have . Assume that and write with . We have
Since , the induction hypothesis yields
Since , it remains to show that . It is enough to show that as power series in . This follows from Lemma 2.7, since
for all .
Proposition
Proof. Fix and with . Let be the map given by
We need to show that for all . By Lemma 2.8, the map is strongly linear, so it suffices to show that for all . Since is injective, it is enough to show that . Now by Lemma 5.13 and by [12, Lemma 8.3]. By Proposition 5.15 and strong linearity, we have
We conclude that .
To conclude our proof of Theorem 4.1, we prove the uniqueness of .
Proposition
Proof. Let be a composition
satisfying conditions
For , we have , so
Thus, it remains to show that .
Using
Likewise .
Now we turn to the task of showing that for
. We make the inductive
assumption that for and , we have (if , this is Proposition 5.5). By
strong linearity, it suffices to verify that for
any monomial . As and likewise for ,
it suffices to show this only for .
Given , we have by
Thus, it suffices to show that for all . By our induction hypothesis, we only need to handle the case that is a successor and . If , then by Proposition 4.9, there is an ordinal with . Our inductive hypothesis and Lemma 2.9 yield
(for ) |
Thus,
(by |
|||
Now suppose and assume by induction that for all .
Take with .
Then
This concludes the proof.
We are now in a position to prove Theorems 1.1 and 1.2. Let be a field of well-based series, let , and let be a function. For and , we define as follows: set , set if , and set if . For with , we define to be the class of series with for all . We say that is a hyperserial field of force if the following axioms are satisfied:
for all , , and .
Axioms
For the remainder of this section, we fix a hyperserial field of force . For
each , we define the function
. The skeleton of
is defined to be the structure
equipped with the real power operation on given
by
Theorem
When , then the skeleton of is just the field itself with the real power operation on . Clearly, this is a hyperserial skeleton, as there are no axioms to verify. Moreover, it is 0-confluent so long as is, so Theorem 6.1 follows from Proposition 5.5, since clearly satisfies , , , and . Therefore, we may assume that . We will verify the various hyperserial skeleton axioms over the next few lemmas, beginning with the Domain of Definition axioms:
Lemma
Proof. By definition, is the
class of with .
Since by
Suppose is a successor. The inclusion holds by definition, so we show the other inclusion. Let
and let .
Take and with . Then , so , by
our inductive assumption. Repeated applications of
Now for the functional equations, asymptotics, regularity, and monotonicity axioms:
Lemma
Proof. Given and , we have
so
so
Lemma
Proof. The axiom
We first consider the case that for some with .
Then
Since , we have , so .
The axiom
Now we handle the case that for all with . We claim that the sets
are mutually cofinal. Let be given and take with and . Then by assumption,
so and
In particular, , as desired.
Before proving the infinite powers axioms, we need a lemma:
Lemma
where is as defined in Subsection 4.1.
Proof. Set ,
so and .
The axiom
We have by
Given , we have , so for , we have
Thus, .
Lemma
Proof. let with , let and let be a sequence of real numbers. We need to show that , where for
and where .
Set . We may assume that and, by negating each if need
be, we further assume that .
Hence is defined. The axioms
so it remains to show that . For each , we have . This gives . Take and with . Lemma 6.5 gives
The axiom
This shows that is a hyperserial skeleton of force . Now we turn to confluence. First, we need a lemma:
Lemma
Proof. The proof is essentially the same as the proof of Lemma 4.8. Take and with . By Lemma 6.5, we have
so . Set , so . Again, Lemma 6.5 gives
so . Now set and fix with . We have
Since , we have .
Lemma
Proof. The skeleton is -confluent since is non-trivial. Let with and assume that is -confluent for all . We also make the inductive assumption that for and , we have for some . Let and take and with . We will show that . We first handle the case that is a successor. Take with . Lemma 6.7 gives . By assumption, we have for some , so , again by Lemma 6.7. Induction on gives for all , so
and . The case that is a limit is similar, though this time we take with and use that
to see that . Since was arbitrary, this gives that is -confluent.
Proof of Theorem 6.1. Lemmas 6.2,
6.3, 6.4, and 6.6 show that of is a hyperserial skeleton.
The composition clearly satisfies
Given a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force
, it is clear that the unique
composition in Theorem 4.1
satisfies all of the hyperserial field axioms except for possibly
Lemma
Thus, the unique composition in Theorem 4.1 satisfies
Theorem
Our goal for Sections 7 and 8 is to prove Theorem 1.3. We will actually prove a “relative” version of the theorem, for which we first need a few more definitions. Given a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force , we let be the composition from Theorem 4.1. For each , we let be the map given by .
Definition
Note that if has force , then is bijective for all .
Remark
Remark
We can now state the relative version of Theorem 1.3 that we are after:
Theorem
Theorem 1.3 follows from Theorem 7.4 by taking . Throughout Section 7 and Subsections 8.1, 8.2, 8.3, and 8.4, we fix a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force and an ordinal , and we make the induction hypothesis that Theorem 7.4 holds for . Note that this holds trivially if . Our main objective is to show that Theorem 7.4 still holds for instead of .
For this, we have to show how to define missing hyperexponentials of the form with . In this section, we start by giving a formula for hyperexponentials that are already defined in . In the next section, we show how to adjoin the missing hyperexponentials to .
Before we continue, let us fix some notation. Let
Given , we set
Note that and that . Given , we set
and we view , , and as functions from to . We define and analogously.
Given , we say that is defined if . If is of force , then is defined for all and . Lemma 4.17 tells us that is strictly increasing; in particular, it is injective. We let be its functional inverse, which is again strictly increasing. We may also consider as a partially defined function on .
Our induction hypothesis, that exists, has the following consequence:
Lemma
Proof. Let with . By our inductive assumption, and both exist in . As and are strictly increasing on and , we have and
In this subsection, we study the range of the functions for and give a formula for their partial functional inverses. We fix and set . We also fix . For , we define series inductively by
Intuitively speaking, behaves like , whereas the sum behaves like for , and thereby provides a functional inverse of on a neighborhood of .
Proposition
Proof. Consider the derivative on . We claim that for all . This is clear for . Assuming that the claim holds for a given , we have
In light of this claim, we have . Recall that has well-based operator support as an operator on , so
Consider the strongly linear map
and set
so is well-based and . For , we have , so for , there exist with
This gives us
and it follows that
As , we have , so we deduce that is well-based and that for .
For our next result, we need a combinatorial lemma for power series over a differential field. Let be a differential field. Then the ring is naturally equipped with two derivations:
We also have a composition given by
for . This composition cooperates with our derivations as follows:
Lemma
for each and , where . Then .
Proof. The last two assumptions give us the following identities
We claim that . Indeed, we have
Write . The identity yields for each . Since , we conclude that and for .
(7.3) |
Proof. We have
Consider the formal power series
Writing , we have
Thus, it suffices to show that .
Let and . Then by factoring out from the inner sum and reindexing, we have
Note that the sequence satisfies the identities:
Since , the sequence satisfies the identities
Setting , we have
Using Lemma 7.7, we conclude that .
Proposition
Proof. Let and let . We have , so
Since , we have
so . This gives .
Conversely, given , Lemma 7.8 yields . Let us show by induction on that . We have . Assuming that , we have
We have
so . This gives
It follows that for each , so . Since , we conclude that .
Definition
In Subsection 3.3, we showed for that the class can be partitioned into convex subclasses , each of which contains a unique -atomic element . In this section, we describe a different partition of into convex subclasses, each of which will contain a unique -truncated series . We will then show that is bijective provided that . This was done in [29] for , but we provide a short proof below. First, for , set , so is 1-truncated and . We also set .
Proposition
Proof. Let and let , and with . We have , since . Thus, we have if and only if , since is an additive subgroup of .
As a related fact for later use, we also note the following:
Lemma
Proof. Given , write , where , , and . We have
so . By Proposition 7.11, .
For the remainder of this subsection, we assume that .
Lemma
Proof. For and , we have and so . Assume now that is a successor and let and . Again, . Take with . Then for all and , we have
so .
Lemma
Proof. We have for all since the series is infinite. Let and let . By Lemma 7.5, the function is strictly increasing, so we have if and only if , hence the result.
By Lemma 7.14 and
Lemma
Proof. Take with . Then Lemma 7.5 gives , so it is enough to prove that . For this, we may show that in . As the map is order-preserving, it is enough to show that
This follows from Lemma 7.5 and the fact that .
Definition
Proposition
Proof. Let . The convexity of follows immediately from the definition of and Lemma 7.5. Let . We claim that , from which it follows by symmetry that . This clearly holds if , so assume that .
We first show that . Let and let with for some . Given with , we have , whence . Therefore,
by Lemma 7.5, so for all such .
If is a successor, take with . Then and since , we have
If is a limit, take with , so that . Let us show that . Suppose for contradiction that . By (2.4), we have
Since , we have , so
Therefore,
This means that : a contradiction since .
Now let and let us show . This is clear if or if , so we assume that , , and are pairwise distinct. By our claim, we have and , so take with and . Note that
thus, . Lemmas 7.5 and 7.15 yield
If , then by definition. If , then , so by our claim.
Proposition
Proof. Let us first show that contains a -truncated element. Suppose that itself is not -truncated, let be greatest such that for some . Setting , we have , so by Lemma 7.15. Our assumption on therefore yields , whence .
We claim that is -truncated. Fix . By definition of , we have for all . Since , Lemma 7.15 gives for all , so . By definition, this means that for all . Since , we have , by Lemma 7.15. Thus, , as claimed.
Now let be -truncated series with . We need to show that . Take with . For , we have since is -truncated. Therefore,
so by Lemma 7.15. Thus . Since , we deduce , so . We also have , so the same argument gives and we conclude that .
For , we define to be the unique -truncated series in . Note that this definition extends the previous definition of . It follows from the proof of Proposition 7.18 that for all and that
Proof. We have if and only if for some . Since for each , this is in turn equivalent to by Lemma 7.5 . Thus, if and only if for some , and it remains to show that for some if and only if for some . This follows from the fact that if , then , so .
Proposition
Proof. Let . Then there is with . Thus, and so by Proposition 7.9. Therefore, by Proposition 7.19.
Corollary
Proof. Let .
Then by Proposition 7.20 and is -truncated
by
Proposition
Proof. We prove this by induction on . Let . By Proposition 7.20, we need only prove that . Let . By Proposition 7.19, there is a with . By Proposition 7.9, there is a with . Since is hyperserial of force , the hyperexponential is defined and
Finally, since , Lemma 4.8 and Proposition 4.9 imply .
Corollary
Corollary
has force .
For all , the function is defined on .
For all and , the hyperexponential is defined for some .
For all , we have .
Proof. The equivalence between ) and ) follows from Proposition 7.22 and the fact that we have
for all . The equivalence between ) and ) follows directly from Proposition 7.22. The equivalence between ) and ) follows from Corollary 7.21.
Throughout this subsection, we let and we set and . Given , it will be convenient to introduce the following notations:
Lemma
Proof. We claim that if , then and
Assuming that , we have
whence . Now
so . Since , we have , so Lemma 7.5 gives
as desired. Composing with gives that if , then and
From which it follows that .
Corollary
Proof. We have . Let with . We have , so
by Lemma 7.5. Since by Lemma 7.25 and is convex, we are done.
Lemma
Proof. Take with . Since , we have by Lemma 7.5. This gives
Thus, . Likewise, since , we have
so . Lemma 7.5 gives , so we have
By Lemma 7.25, both and are elements of . Since is convex, this means that it also contains and .
We have the following useful consequence:
Corollary
Proof. Take with . Then
We have by Lemma 7.27 and we have by Lemma 7.25, so . Likewise, . Since is convex, this yields . Since by Lemma 7.27, we conclude that .
Corollary
Proof. As is strictly increasing, we have , which gives . We first claim that . If , then Corollary 7.28 gives that , so we may focus on the case when . Suppose towards contradiction that and that for some . Then
Since , we have , so . Since , we have
so by Proposition 7.19, a contradiction.
From our claim, we get . This yields , as . Take with . Lemma 7.25 gives
so since is convex and is strictly increasing.
In this section, is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force and . Given we consider a class of -truncated series without -hyperexponentials in and show how to extend into a minimal confluent hyperserial skeleton of force that contains for all series . Most of the work in the case has already been done in [29], but Subsection 8.1 contains a self-contained treatment for our setting. For the construction of in Subsections 8.1, 8.2, 8.3, and 8.4, we recall that we made the induction hypothesis that Theorem 7.4 holds for . After the construction of , we conclude this section with the proofs of Theorems 7.4 and 1.3.
Let be the class of all 1-truncated series for which is not defined. Let be a non-empty subclass of and let be the -subspace of generated by and . By Lemma 7.12, consists only of 1-truncated series.
We let be the restriction of to . Note the following:
We claim that satisfies
By definition, we have if and only if , so
satisfies
Since for ,
the axiom
Extending . For with , we have if and only if , so if and only if if and only if . Accordingly, we set
This ensures that holds. Note that if , then , so and . Thus, and . We also have the following:
For , we have
so satisfies .
For , we have , since . Thus
which proves .
satisfies .
To see this, let with
and let . We want to show
that . Since and by
Since and since satisfies , we have
Let . Since and satisfies , the hyperlogarithm is -truncated by Lemma 7.14. It follows from Lemma 7.13 that is also -truncated, so satisfies .
Let and let be a sequence of real numbers. To show that satisfies , we need to show that the sum is in . We have
Since and since satisfies , we have . It remains to note that and that is closed under finite sums.
Since and are both monomials, they must be equal. The axiom gives .
Now , , , , and hold for each , since they hold in . Furthermore, holds if ; this is clear if and the above proof of still goes through when . Thus, is a hyperserial skeleton of force which extends .
Proposition
Proof. Clearly, is -confluent. Let and take with . We have . Let and take with . We have and, by assumption, , so
By definition, implies , so . We have
so and, more generally, for . Thus, the skeleton is -confluent.
Let us summarize:
Proposition
Using the composition from Theorem 4.1, we can check whether an embedding of confluent hyperserial skeletons is of force without having to verify that for all .
Lemma
Proof. We will show by induction on that . For , this holds as is order-preserving. Let and assume that for all . If is a limit, then by , we have
Suppose is a successor and let . We have for all by . Our induction hypothesis gives for all . Applying again gives , so .
Proposition
of force that extends .
Proof. As is hyperserial of force , we have an external composition . Since , is -linear, and is an -subspace of containing , we have .
Since , we have so . Thus, is a monomial for by Lemma 7.12. We define a map by setting
It is routine to check that is an embedding of ordered monomial groups with -powers. By Proposition 2.3, this embedding uniquely extends into a strongly linear field embedding of into , which we will still denote by . Note that if , then , so extends .
We now prove that is a force embedding. By Lemma 8.3, we need only show that commutes with logarithms and hyperlogarithms. Given , we have
Now let with and let . If , then , so we automatically have , since extends . If , then , so
Let us finally assume that is another embedding of force that extends . To see that , it suffices to show that for . Now
so .
From this point until Subsection 8.5, we let and set
Note that if is a successor and if is a limit. Let be the class of all -truncated series for which is not defined. Let be a non-empty subclass of . Consider and . We have by Corollary 7.21. Since contains a unique -truncated element, is -truncated and , it follows that . Thus, we have
If is a successor, then let be the smallest class containing such that whenever and . By Lemma 7.13, the class also consists only of -truncated series. If is a limit, then set . Note that . For the remainder of this subsection (with the exception of Proposition 8.30) we assume that .
Remark
so . In particular, .
We define the group as follows. If is a limit, then is the group generated by the elements with and satisfying the relations . Hence is the group of products
of is finite. If is a successor, then let be the equivalence relation on defined by
We let be the group of formal products
for which the hypersupport is well-based and is finite. Given , we note that , whence . Hence is indeed a group.
For , we define and . We set if , which happens if and only if . The following facts will be used frequently, where range over :
for ,
, and if then
If or , then ,
If and or if and then .
Let denote the direct product . We denote by a general element of this group, where we implicitly understand that and ; we also identify and with and , respectively. In the special case when , we write .
Remark
Nevertheless, we may construct a privileged representation as a finite product as follows. Since is finite, there exist with for and . Since is well-based, we may also take for all . Then
Fix and set . For each , we have , so
Set
This gives us the finite representation
Note that .
(I) | |||
(II) | |||
(III) | |||
(IV) |
We define the relation on by if and only if .
Proposition
Proof. By definition, the relation extends the orderings on and . In order to show that is an order, it suffices to check that is a total positive cone on .
Let . By the definition of and the fact that , it is clear that and cannot both be in . Let us show that either or . Assume that . If and or and , then satisfies (III) or (IV). Suppose that , , and . Then since , so . Since and , we conclude that satisfies (II). If , , and then satisfies (I), for similar reasons.
Now let . We will show that . If both and satisfy one of the last two rules, then this is clear. Thus, we may assume without loss of generality that satisfies either rule (I) or rule (II). We consider the following cases:
Case 1: and both satisfy (I) or they both satisfy (II). Suppose that they both satisfy (I). Then and , so we need to verify that . By Corollary 7.26, we have . Since , we also have , whence . The case when and both satisfy (II) is similar.
Case 2: satisfies (I) and satisfies (III) or (IV). We have , so if , then satisfies (IV). Suppose that . If , then and if , then , so as is strictly increasing. Since satisfies rule (I) and , we have
so satisfies (I).
Case 3: satisfies (II) and satisfies (III) or (IV). We have , so if , then satisfies (IV). Suppose that . If , then , so and . Since satisfies rule (II), we have , so
Hence satisfies (II).
Case 4: One of the monomials and satisfies (I) and the other one satisfies (II). Without loss of generality, we may assume that satisfies (I) and satisfies (II). Let us first consider the case when . Then , so and . Since and , we deduce that , so by Corollary 7.29. Since satisfies (II), we have , so
and satisfies (II).
Let us now consider the case when . If , then satisfies (III). If and , then satisfies (IV). If , then , so , contradicting that . It remains to consider the case that . Then , so as is strictly increasing. Since and , we deduce that , so . Since , we have , so . This gives
so satisfies (I).
Remark
Since , we also have . More generally, for , we have
This is because by Corollary 7.28 with .
It is easy to check that this defines a real power operation on . Note that for each non-zero .
Now that we have defined an ordering and a real power operation on , we let . Then is a field of well-based series extending . When , we write .
In this subsection, we extend the hyperlogarithms from to , while verifying that they satisfy the axioms for hyperserial skeletons. We separate various cases as a function of , including the case of the ordinary logarithm when .
In each case, we start with the definition of the domain of the extended hyperlogarithm on and then define on the elements of which do not already lie in . We next check that satisfies the domain definition axioms , as well as the other axioms for hyperserial skeletons.
We extend to by setting
for . Note that if and only if . We claim that is well-defined. Let and be as in Remark 8.6, so and
Each sum exists in , since the support is a strictly decreasing sequence in . Thus, is well-defined. If , then we note that
Finally, we extend log to all of by setting
. We let
be the restriction of to the class , so satisfies
Using the definition of real powers, it is straightforward to check that
satisfies
for and
Lemma
Proof. Given , we must show that . We proceed by case distinction:
If , then since satisfies
If , then and
If , then and . Thus since . If , then , so Remark 8.8 again yields . In either case, .
Suppose , , and . We have , so it is enough to show that and . We have
by Lemma 7.25, so , whence and . Since , we also have , so
Suppose , , and . This time, we need to show that and . Using that and that , we have , so
If and , then . So the result follows from the fact that and .
Lemma
Proof. Given ,
we need to show that . If
, then
so since satisfies
we have . If , then .
Consider now the case that , , and . Since , we need to show that . For each , we have
by Lemma 7.25. As , this gives . If , then we have
by Remark 8.8. If , so is defined in , then for each , we have
since is strictly increasing. As is arbitrary, this gives .
Finally, suppose , , and . The same argument as above gives for , so and .
This sum is well-defined, as for . For , we set
This sum is also well-defined, as is well-based and for all , and with . If , then note that , so
and whenever . Finally, we extend to all of by setting
for . As before, we let be the restriction of to
, so
satisfies
The axiom (and thus ) follow easily from the definition of and the axiom
Lemma
Proof. We have for and for . It follows that for so long as .
Suppose that , , and .
Then , so it is enough to
show that . As shown in the
argument that
Given with , we decompose , and define
Note that and whenever is a limit ordinal. More generally, we have
whenever (including the case when ).
Lemma
Proof. We prove this by induction on , beginning with . Let , so
If , then either or . If , then if and only if . If , then if and only if . It remains to note that for all .
Now assume that and that holds for all . Since satisfies for each , we may focus on elements of the form where and . For the remainder of the proof, we fix such an element. If is a successor, then we need to show that if and only if . One direction is clear: if then for each . For the other direction, if , then , so write and note that is a monomial if and only if . If is a limit, then for all if and only if , so we have if and only if for all .
Lemma
Proof. Let and with and . Since satisfies for each , it suffices to show that . Decomposing , we have , so
Let , let , and let . We note that has no infinitesimal terms in its support, so is satisfied since it holds in . To see that satisfies , suppose that is a successor and write . Then
Lemma
Proof. Let with , let with , and let . We want to show that
If , then this holds because satisfies . Consider the following cases:
If and , then write and . We have
Since , we have . If , then . If , then , so either or and . In both cases, we have .
If and , then we must have by Remark 8.8. Writing , we have , so . By Corollary 7.28, we have , so
again by Remark 8.8. In particular, .
If and , then . Arguing as in the previous case, we have .
Lemma
Proof. Let and let be a sequence of real numbers. Consider the sum . We need to show that . If , then . Suppose with . Then for all , so
where .
Note that implies for some . Moreover, if is a limit, then . In other words,
We define
The proofs of Lemmas 8.12 and 8.15 can be amended to show that satisfies and ; just replace with . Since satisfies , , and , it suffices to check these axioms for elements of the form , where and . If , then and if , then is -truncated by Lemma 7.13 (recall that is a successor), whence by Corollary 7.21. In either case, we have , so satisfies . As for , suppose that is a successor. We have
if and we have
otherwise.
Lemma
Proof. Let , , and . If , then we have
If , then . Since , we have by Remark 8.8.
Lemma
Proof. Let with and let . We need to show that
We proceed by case distinction.
If , then this holds because satisfies .
Suppose and for some and some . Then
If , then either or and . In either case, we have . If and , then so
by Remark 8.8. A similar argument handles the case that and . Finally, if and , then again, either or and . In the first case, we have , so since both and are monomials by Lemma 7.13 and Corollary 7.21. In the second case, we have since and .
Suppose for some and some and . Then since . For each , we have by Lemma 7.25, so . If , then by Remark 8.8. Hence,
If , then since is strictly increasing. Since is arbitrary, this gives , so
Suppose and for some and some . Then , so similar arguments as above give for each . Again, we conclude that
Lemma
Proof. If , let , with . We have
If , then either or . If , then if and only if . If , then if and only if . By Remark 8.5, we have
for all , where by Lemma 7.13 and Corollary 7.21.
If is a successor, then let and . We need to show that if and only if . This holds since
and since whenever , by Corollary 7.21.
Finally, if is a non-zero limit, then we use that
To see that
Let . Since is -truncated, we have . This gives for . If , then is also -truncated by Lemma 7.13, so since . This gives if . If , then since is strictly increasing. Since is a monomial by Corollary 7.21, this gives . In all three cases, we have , so
as desired.
If is a successor, then either or . In both cases,
so
Lemma
Proof. Let and let . We want to show that
Note that . We claim that
. If , then this follows from the fact that satisfies
Now suppose towards contradiction that . We will show that . As is the unique -truncated element in and is -truncated, this is a contradiction.
Since by , we have , so
By
If , then Lemma 7.5 gives
so . Suppose and let with . If , then
so by Remark 8.8. As , this too gives . Finally, if , then
so by Remark 8.8. As , we have
so once again.
Lemma
Proof. Let and let be a sequence of real numbers. Consider the sum . If ,
then since satisfies
where . If is a successor, then we may write
If for all , then
where . If for some , then let be minimal with . We have , where
Note that
so it remains to show that .
Since by Lemma 7.13 and Corollary
7.21, this follows from the fact that
satisfies
For , we have if and only if since . This proves that satisfies . Let . We have
so is satisfied. As for , it suffices to show that
since for all by
Now for , let . Since by
it is enough to show that . This holds because satisfies and .
Lemma
Proof. Let with and let . We want to show that . Since and likewise for , it is enough to show that
We proceed by case distinction:
If , then the result follows from for .
If and , then
Since and satisfies , we have
If and , then . Since and satisfies , we have
Thus,
If and , then the argument is similar to the previous case.
Proof. Let and let be a sequence of real numbers. We need to show that the sum is in . If , then . If for some , then
We have , since satisfies
since and satisfies . We conclude by noting that is closed under addition.
Remark
and the proof of Lemma 8.22 also tells us that satisfies .
Lemma
Proof. It suffices [
Since and are both monomials, they must be equal. The axiom gives , a contradiction.
For all with , the axioms , , , and automatically hold in since they hold in , as does the axiom if is an ordinal.
We have completed the proof of the following:
Proposition
Let us finally examine the confluence and universality of .
Proposition
Proof. Clearly, is -confluent. Consider and write . By our definition of , we either have have or . If , then and, more generally, for all with , since by Lemma 3.7. Assume from now on that .
We set and . For , let us first show by induction that
If , then and
so we indeed have . Let and suppose that for . If and is a successor, then our induction hypothesis yields
Writing , we have
so
If and is a limit, then there is such that . For this , we have
so . Finally, if and is a successor, then , where if is a limit. This gives
In both cases, we have , so , since .
Let us now show that exists. Let , so by our assumption that . Take with . We have , so
Since is an infinite monomial, it is -truncated, so so long as it is defined. Thus, is either equal to or .
If , then for with . On the other hand, if , then
Take with . Then
so and, more generally, when and .
Propositions 8.25 and 8.26 yield:
Corollary
Remark
Given and , we have . Given , we have .
Let us now show that satisfies a universal property. We start with a lemma.
Lemma
Proof. Choose and such that . Then and so it suffices to show that . Since are monomials and , we have
The monotonicity of gives . We conclude that , since and are monomials.
Proposition
of force that extends .
Proof. Since is confluent, we have an external composition . We first claim that . If is a limit, then so there is nothing to show. If is a successor, then for , there is with . We have
so . Having shown our claim, we may assume without loss of generality that .
Given , the series is -truncated, so is -atomic, by Remark 7.21. We set . Note that for and , the series
exists in by
If is a successor, let and be as in Remark 8.6. We define
Note that in both the limit and successor case, we have
Given and , we have by Lemma 8.29 and, if , then . Thus, for . In particular, is order preserving, since
Next, we extend to all of by setting for . Note that extends . It is straightforward to check that is an embedding of monomial groups which respects real powers. We need to show that preserves the order. Let . If both , then . This leaves us two cases to consider:
Suppose , , and . Set . We claim that . If , then , so this follows from Lemma 7.25. If , then , so this follows from Lemmas 7.25 and 7.27. In either case, we have , so . From this, we see that
so Since , this gives . Thus
so .
Suppose , , and . Set . As before, Lemmas 7.25 and 7.27 give , so
Since , this gives , so
and .
By Proposition 2.3, the function extends uniquely into a strongly linear strictly increasing embedding , which we still denote by .
We claim that is an embedding of force . By Lemma 8.3, we need only show that commutes with logarithms and hyperlogarithms. We begin with logarithms. Let and . If , then for some and
If , then
If , then and
If , then
In all cases, we have, . For , we have
Now, let and let . Note that , so we need to show that . Write . If , then
If , then . If , then
If , then
If , then and
If , then and
Since for and since for , this completes the proof of our claim that is an embedding of force .
We finish with the uniqueness of . Let be another embedding of force that extends . To see that , we only need to show that for all . For , we have
so . For , we deduce that
Since is strongly linear, this gives for , so by the injectivity of .
In this subsection, we prove Theorem 7.4. Recall that is a confluent hyperserial skeleton of force .
Definition
.
if is a successor.
if is a non-zero limit.
if .
We set , so and we have the force inclusion whenever or and . We set
Note that by Lemma 2.1. Note also that and . Theorem 7.4 is a consequence of the next two propositions:
Proposition
Proof. By Corollary 7.24, it suffices to show that
for . Fix and fix . Fix also a limit ordinal with . Then so either exists in or exists in . In either case, .
Proposition
Proof. We will show for each and each that there is a unique force embedding extending . We have , so suppose that we have defined this unique embedding when , and when , . If is a successor, then , so by Proposition 8.4 (if ) or Proposition 8.30 (if ), the embedding extends uniquely to an embedding
Since uniquely extends and since uniquely extends , we see that uniquely extends . If is a limit, then we set . The map is only defined on , which may not equal , but is defined on all of and so extends uniquely to a force embedding , which we also denote by . As each uniquely extends , we see that uniquely extends as well. Likewise, we define to be the unique force embedding extending .
Theorem 7.4 follows from Propositions 8.32 and 8.33.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. On numbers, germs, and transseries. In Proc. Int. Cong. of Math. 2018, volume 1, pages 1–24. Rio de Janeiro, 2018.
M. Aschenbrenner, L. van den Dries, and J. van der Hoeven. The surreal numbers as a universal -field. J. Eur. Math. Soc., 21(4):1179–1199, 2019.
V. Bagayoko, J. van der Hoeven, and V. Mantova. Defining a surreal hyperexponential. Technical Report, HAL, 2020. http://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02861485.
A. Berarducci and V. Mantova. Surreal numbers, derivations and transseries. Technical Report http://arxiv.org/abs/1503.00315, Arxiv, 2015.
É. Borel. Leçons sur les séries divergentes. Gauthier-Villars, 2-nd edition, 1928. Reprinted by Jacques Gabay.
M. Boshernitzan. Hardy fields, existence of transexponential functions. Æquationes Math., 30:258–280, 1986.
N. Bourbaki. Fonctions d'une variable réelle. Éléments de Mathématiques (Chap. 5). Hermann, 2-nd edition, 1961.
B. I. Dahn and P. Göring. Notes on exponential-logarithmic terms. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 127:45–50, 1986.
L. van den Dries. Tame topology and o-minimal structures, volume 248 of London Math. Soc. Lect. Note. Cambridge University Press, 1998.
L. van den Dries and Ph. Ehrlich. Fields of surreal numbers and exponentiation. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 167(2):173–188, 2001.
L. van den Dries, J. van der Hoeven, and E. Kaplan. Logarithmic hyperseries. Trans. of the AMS, 372(7):5199–5241, 2019.
L. van den Dries, A. Macintyre, and D. Marker. Logarithmic-exponential power series. Journal of the London Math. Soc., 56(2):417–434, 1997.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Sur la grandeur relative des infinis des fonctions. Annali di Matematica Pura ed Applicata (1867-1897), 4(1):338–353, 1870.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über asymptotische Werte, infinitäre Approximationen und infinitäre Auflösung von Gleichungen. Math. Ann., 8:363–414, 1875.
P. du Bois-Reymond. Über die Paradoxen des Infinitärscalcüls. Math. Ann., 11:149–167, 1877.
J. Écalle. Introduction aux fonctions analysables et preuve constructive de la conjecture de Dulac. Hermann, collection: Actualités mathématiques, 1992.
H. Gonshor. An Introduction to the Theory of Surreal Numbers. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1986.
H. Hahn. Über die nichtarchimedischen Größensysteme. Sitz. Akad. Wiss. Wien, 116:601–655, 1907.
G. H. Hardy. Orders of infinity. Cambridge Univ. Press, 1910.
G. H. Hardy. Properties of logarithmico-exponential functions. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 10(2):54–90, 1911.
D. Harvey and J. van der Hoeven. Faster polynomial multiplication over finite fields using cyclotomic coefficient rings. Accepted for publication in J. of Complexity, 2019.
J. van der Hoeven. Automatic asymptotics. PhD thesis, École polytechnique, Palaiseau, France, 1997.
J. van der Hoeven. Transséries fortement monotones. Chapter 1 of unpublished CNRS activity report, https://www.texmacs.org/joris/schmeling/rap1-2000.pdf, 2000.
J. van der Hoeven. Operators on generalized power series. Journal of the Univ. of Illinois, 45(4):1161–1190, 2001.
J. van der Hoeven. Transseries and real differential algebra, volume 1888 of Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, 2006.
J. van der Hoeven. Transserial Hardy fields. In Felipe Cano, Frank Loray, Juan José Moralez-Ruiz, Paulo Sad, and Mark Spivakovsky, editors, Differential Equations and Singularities. 60 years of J. M. Aroca, volume 323 of Astérisque, pages 453–487. SMF, 2009.
H. Kneser. Reelle analytische Lösungen der Gleichung und verwandter Funktionalgleichungen. Jour. f. d. reine und angewandte Math., 187(1/2):56–67, 1950.
M. C. Schmeling. Corps de transséries. PhD thesis, Université Paris-VII, 2001.
class of ordinal numbers 7
or 7
if is a successor, if is a limit 7
for each exponent of 7
for each exponent of 7
unique ordinal with and 7
field of well-based series over 8
set of monomials with 8
dominant monomial of 8
is a truncation of 9
operator support of 10
relative support of 10
to the power 10
field of logarithmic hyperseries 11
formal hyperlogarithm of strength 11
group of logarithmic monomials of strength 11
field of logarithmic series of strength 12
group of logarithmic (hyper)monomials 12
derivation on 12
-th derivative of 12
for , unique series with 13
hyperlogarithm of force 14
axiom of domain definition 14
class of -atomic elements 14
axiom of functional equations 15
axiom of asymptotics 15
axiom of monotonicity 15
axiom of regularity 15
axiom of transfinite products 15
projection 16
class of series with 16
class of series with 16
Taylor expansion of at 20
Taylor expansion of at 20
axioms for hyperserial fields 36
minimal extension of of force 40
(partially defined) functional inverse of 41
class of -truncated series 44
unique -truncated series in 47
minimal extension of with 50
group of monomials for 50
class of series 53
formal adjunction of to a field 54
group of formal products 54
-atomic element 14
Cantor normal form 7
coefficient of an ordinal 7
-confluent field 16
confluent hyperserial field 36
confluent hyperserial skeleton 17
confluent hyperserial skeleton of force 40
dominant monomial 8
embedding of force 16
exponent of an ordinal 7
extension of force 16
field of well-based series 8
hyperserial field 36
hypersupport 54
infinitesimal series 9
logarithmic hyperseries 11
monomial group 8
operator support 10
positive infinite series 9
real powering operation 10
relatively well-based function 10
strongly linear function 9
support of a series 8
-truncated series 44
truncation of a series 9
well-based family of series 9
well-based function 9
well-based series 8
well-based set 8